Cover of The Review of Metaphysics
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 61-80 of 135 documents


book reviews
61. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Timothy Fuller Smith, Steven D., The Disenchantment of Secular Discourse
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
62. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Arnd Bohm Spencer, Vicki A., Herder’s Political Thought: A Study of Language, Culture, and Community
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
63. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Paolo C. Biondi Thagard, Paul., The Cognitive Science of Science: Explanation, Discovery, and Conceptual Change
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
64. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Diana Siclovan Thomas, Paul., Karl Marx. Critical Lives
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
65. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Roger P. Alford Waldron, Jeremy., “Partly Laws Common to All Mankind”: Foreign Law in American Courts
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
66. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Paul Thomas Waldron, Jeremy., The Harm in Hate Speech: The Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
67. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Jude P. Dougherty Watanabe, Morimichi., Nicholas of Cusa: A Companion to His Life and Times
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
68. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Joseph Trullinger Wood, David W., “Mathesis of the Mind”: A Study of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre and Geometry: Fichte-Studien-Supplementa, vol. 29
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
69. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Reviewer Index
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
70. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Abstracts
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
71. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Announcements
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
72. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
May Sim Rethinking Honor with Aristotle and Confucius
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Confucius and Aristotle share the conviction that the virtuous deserves honor. While Aristotle thinks that the completely virtuous person should make claims to the honor he rightly deserves, Confucius maintains that he should be humble and disregard such claims. This radical opposition between Aristotle and Confucius about the good man’s attitude toward honor provides a case for examining the exemplary person for them. The author considers the reasons for their differences by focusing on the following questions: Who accords the honor? Does honor have any effect on the good man’s actions, attitudes, virtues and self-knowledge? Whose account is superior? And to which criteria should we appeal for adjudicating Aristotle’s and Confucius’ contradictory claims? Focusing on ‘pride’, the author examines if the virtue of honor which gives rise to these rival claims in Aristotle and Confucius can provide the resources for resolving their conflicts.
73. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Thom Brooks Punishment and Moral Sentiments
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What is the relationship between our moral sentiments and the justification of punishment? One position is that our moral sentiments provide for punishment’s justification. This article’s focus is on Adam Smith’s theory of punishment and the role that moral sentiments play in this theory. The author argues that commentators have been mistaken to view Smith’s position as essentially retributivist. Instead, Smith defends a unified theory where punishment serves retributivist, deterrent, and rehabilitative goals. The author then concludes with some critical remarks on how well this theory speaks to contemporary concerns.
74. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
William E. Mann Locating the Lost Island
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article replies to Lynne Rudder Baker and Gareth B. Matthews’s “Anselm’s Argument Reconsidered,” in which the authors claim to have produced a sound version of Anselm’s ontological argument. Using Gaunilo’s “lost island” counterexample, this article explores the question whether an Anselmian argument can prove the existence of the greatest conceivable being without relying on premises that also prove the existence of the greatest conceivable island. A premise crucial to any such argument is a “greatness principle,” about which there has recently been scholarly disagreement. This article examines two versions: (GP′) If it is in the understanding alone, it can be conceived to exist in reality also, which is greater, and (GP*) If it exists in the understanding alone, that which is greater can be conceived to exist in reality also. A distinctive feature of Baker and Matthews’s approach is that it countenances some “objects of thought” that not only do not exist in reality but logically cannot exist in reality. They then argue that for any conceivable island, a greater island is conceivable, but that there cannot be a conceivable being greater than the greatest conceivable being. Their strategy is vulnerable on two counts. It does not address the possibility that there is no upper limit to greatness in conceivable beings. Nor does it assure us that the greatest conceivable being is even logically possible. Thus their version of Anselm’s argument is inconclusive.
75. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Ariberto Acerbi Aquinas’s Commentary on Boethius’s De Trinitate
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The author seeks to clarify the theoretical relevance of a problem developed by Aquinas in his Commentary on Boethius’ De Trinitate: how can our intellect recognize the ontological and epistemic priority of a sense substance? The difficulty seems to arise from the Platonic vinculation among intelligibility, necessity, and universality, and therefore from the opposition between intellegibility and the main properties of the sense substance: individuality and becoming. The coherence of Aquinas's solution is here examined: how to maintain the Aristotelian vinculation among being, individuality, and activity with the Platonic assumption about the ontological and epistemic priority of the form. A solution is offered by the author regarding the capacity of the human intellect to go beyond the representation of the formal dimension of being in order to perceive its existential dimension. This solution (here only sketched) suggests the metaphysical consistency of human experience.
critical study
76. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Phillip Stambovsky Idealism, Scientia Intuitiva, and Scientific Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
“Considered objectively, there can be only one human reason, there . . . can be only one true system of philosophy from principles, in however many different and even conflicting ways one has philosophized about the same proposition”—so declares Kant in the Vorrede to the “Doctrine of Right.” Kant makes this observation in the process of framing a striking claim: “prior to the development of critical philosophy there had been no philosophy at all.” Eckart Förster adduces this claim as a point of departure for undertaking “to grasp and understand the single [sic] thought” that orients his ambitious new study, Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction. It is thus with reference to Kant’s pronouncement that Förster propounds his book’s lead thought, or at least the first part of it: “philosophy begins in 1781 and ends in 1806,” this in the sense that over those twenty-five years “philosophy became a science, thereby also arriving at knowledge of itself.” Förster sets himself the task of elucidating the “internal dynamic” of the “fundamental idea” that informs the philosophical-historical thesis to which he keys his investigation. The fundamental idea in question is the classic speculative problematic of objective knowledge, which in the Kantian context of Förster’s study takes the form of the issue of how it is that we know (discursively, intuitively) “the supersensible substrate of appearances.” Beyond simply anatomizing this issue, however, the author engages “to reproduce its immanent development,” systematically “reconstructing” it through interlinked analyses of seminal writings of Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Goethe, and Hegel.
book reviews
77. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Mario DeCaro Auxier, Randall E. and Lewis Hahn, eds. The Philosophy of Richard Rorty
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
78. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Leo J. Elders Bastit, Michel. La substance: Essai métaphysique
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
79. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Christopher Richards Berofsky, Bernard. Nature’s Challenge to Free Will
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
80. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 2
Donald C. Lindenmuth Brann, Eva, Peter Kalkavage, and Eric Salem. Plato Statesman
view |  rights & permissions | cited by