Cover of Teaching Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 81-100 of 3204 documents


book reviews
81. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Robert C. Robinson Doing Ethics: Moral Reasoning, Theory, and Contemporary Issues, 6th edition, by Lewis Vaughn
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
82. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Theordore Stone The Democracy Reader: From Classical to Contemporary Philosophy, edited by Steven M. Cahn, Andrew T. Forechimes and Robert B. Talisse
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
83. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Sandra Tomsons Applied Ethics: An Impartial Introduction, by Elizabeth Jackson, Tyron Goldschmidt, Dustin Crummett, and Rebecca Chan
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
84. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Galen Barry Facts vs. Opinions: Helping Students Overcome the Distinction
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many students struggle to enter moral debates in a productive way because they automatically think of moral claims as ‘just opinions’ and not something one could productively argue about. Underlying this response are various versions of a muddled distinction between ‘facts’ and ‘opinions.’ This paper outlines a way to help students overcome their use of this distinction, thereby clearing an obstacle to true moral debate. It explains why the fact-opinion distinction should simply be scrapped, rather than merely sharpened. It then proposes a different distinction well suited to replace it. Finally, it outlines an activity which can be used to teach the new distinction, as well as a number of benefits to attempting the whole replacement process.
85. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
C. D. Brewer Proof Golf: A Logic Game
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Here I describe a game that I use in my logic classes once we begin derivations. The game can help improve class dynamics, help struggling students recognizes they are not alone, open lines of communication between students, and help students of all levels prepare for exams. The game can provide struggling students with more practice with the fundamental rules of a logical system while also challenging students who excel at derivations. If students are struggling with particular rules or strategies in the system, the game can be tailored to address them. I explain how the game has evolved since I started using it, highlighting the pedagogical benefits of the changes I have made, and (in the appendix) I provide examples of the handouts I distribute and a “checklist” to use before, during, and after the game.
86. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Thomas Metcalf The Case for Philosophy as a General-Education Requirement
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that colleges should include philosophy courses as general-education requirements. I begin by explaining the prima facie case against general-education requirements and the need for philosophers to defend their courses’ place in the general-education curriculum. Next, I present two arguments for philosophy as a general-education requirement. The first is the Argument from Content: that philosophy courses’ content tends to match the intended nature and purposes of general-education courses. The second is the Argument from Outcomes: that even if philosophy courses didn’t match the intended purposes of general-education courses, they would still be appropriate as general-education requirements, because there is empirical evidence that philosophy courses produce valuable skills and knowledge in students.
87. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jeff Mitchell On the Invidious Distinction Between Weak and Strong Critical Thinking
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The distinction between weak and strong forms of critical thinking is a hallmark of Richard Paul’s pedagogy. He maintains that good reasoning entails a personal commitment to fair-mindedness. In this brief essay, I argue that Paul’s conception of fair-mindedness conflates cognitive empathy with empathetic concern and altruism. One’s understanding another’s perspective by no means entails approving of it, and one may seek to better grasp this standpoint for purely selfish reasons. Depending upon the circumstances, the other could be one’s competitor, enemy, mark, or even intended victim. This implies that while we may wish that the world were otherwise, even very bad people can be highly effective critical thinkers.
88. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jake Wright An Argument for Asynchronous Course Delivery in the Early Stages of the COVID-19 Pandemic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that campus closures and shifts to online instruction in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic created an obligation to offer courses asynchronously. This is because some students could not have reasonably foreseen circumstances making continued synchronous participation impossible. Offering synchronous participation options to students who could continue to participate thusly would have been unfair to students who could not participate synchronously. I also discuss why ex post facto consideration of this decision is warranted, noting that similar actions may be necessary in the future and that other tough pedagogical cases share important similarities with this case.
book reviews
89. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Patrick D. Anderson Rick and Morty and Philosophy: In the Beginning Was the Squanch. Edited by Lester C. Abesamis and Wayne Yuen
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
90. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Errol Ball Philosophy of Science: The Key Thinkers, second edition. Edited by James Robert Brown
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
91. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Teresa Baron Stem Cells: A Very Short Introduction, 2nd edition. By Jonathan Slack
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
92. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Patrick Brissey Doing Practical Ethics. By Ian Stoner and Jason Swartwood
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
93. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Brett A. Fulkerson-Smith The Excellent Mind: Intellectual Virtues for Everyday Life. By Nathan L. King
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
94. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Andy Hakim Syllabus: The Remarkable, Unremarkable Document That Changes Everything. By William Germano and Kit Nicholls
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
95. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Fraser Landry Higher Expectations: Can Colleges Teach Students What They Need to Know in the 21st Century? By Derek Bok
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
96. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Daniel Massey The Craft of College Teaching: A Practical Guide. By Robin DiYanni and Anton Borst
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
97. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Senem Saner From Marx to Hegel and Back: Capitalism, Critique, and Utopia. Edited by Victoria Fareld and Hannes Kuch
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
98. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Bart Schultz Gareth B. Matthews, The Child’s Philosopher. Edited by Maughn Rollins Gregory and Megan Jane Laverty
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
99. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 2
Christopher Cowley Teaching Medical Ethics through Medical Law
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Medical ethics is normally taught in a combination of three ways: through discussions of normative theories and principles; through for-and-against debating of topics; or through case studies (narrative ethics). I want to argue that a fourth approach might be better, and should be used more: teaching medical ethics through medical law. Medical law is already deeply imbued with ethical concepts, principles and reasons, and allows the discussion of ethics through the “back door,” as it were. The two greatest advantages of the law are (i) its familiar authority, especially among the disengaged medical students who have little interest or respect for the subject of ethics; and (ii) its focus on the reality of the people and the tragedies discussed (as opposed to the abstractness of a lot of ethical discussion). Finally, I argue that medical law, unlike ethics, allows more efficient and more detailed MCQ assessment.
100. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 2
Robert Schroer Teaching Students Some Cognitive Science to Evaluate Weird Perceptual Experiences: Some Advantages of the “We See What Our Evolutionary Ancestors Needed to See” Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
How can we use what cognitive science has taught us about perception to improve the critical thinking skills of our students? What, for instance, does it tell us about subjects who think they’ve seen Bigfoot, ghosts, and other “weird things”? I explore two approaches for giving students some empirically based tools for examining cases like these. The first, which I call the “we see what we want to see” approach, focuses the idea that beliefs and desires can shape our visual experiences. This approach, however, encourages students to view subjects who report weird experiences as being cognitively irresponsible and worthy of derision. The second approach, which I call the “we see what our evolutionary ancestors needed to see” approach, asserts these experiences are the result of evolutionarily designed perceptual mechanisms that specialize in representing human-like qualities. Fortunately, the second approach does not create the same problematic attitude in students as the first.