Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 341-360 of 4937 documents

0.181 sec

341. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 7
Darren Bradley A Relevant Alternatives Solution to the Bootstrapping and Self-Knowledge Problems
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The main argument given for relevant alternatives theories of knowledge has been that they answer scepticism about the external world. I will argue that relevant alternatives also solve two other problems that have been much discussed in recent years, a) the bootstrapping problem and b) the apparent conflict between semantic externalism and armchair self-knowledge. Furthermore, I will argue that scepticism and Mooreanism can be embedded within the relevant alternatives framework.
342. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 7
Jan Almäng Tense as a Feature of Perceptual Content
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In recent years the idea that perceptual content is tensed in the sense that we can perceive objects as present or as past has come under attack. In this paper the notion of tensed content is to the contrary defended. The paper argues that assuming that something like an intentionalistic theory of perception is correct, it is very reasonable to suppose that perceptual content is tensed, and that a denial of this notion requires a denial of some intuitively very plausible principles. The paper discusses some common objections against the notion of tensed content and concludes that none of them succeeds in showing that perceptual content cannot be tensed.
343. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 8
Matthew Braham, Martin van Hees The Impossibility of Pure Libertarianism
344. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 8
Kai Hauser, W. Hugh Woodin Strong Axioms of Infinity and the Debate About Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One of the most distinctive and intriguing developments of modern set theory has been the realization that, despite widely divergent incentives for strengthening the standard axioms, there is essentially only one way of ascending the higher reaches of infinity. To the mathematical realist the unexpected convergence suggests that all these axiomatic extensions describe different aspects of the same underlying reality.
345. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 9/10
Amie L. Thomasson Quizzical Ontology and Easy Ontology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines what’s at stake in which form of metaontological deflationism we adopt. Stephen Yablo has argued for a ‘quizzicalist’ approach, holding that many ontological questions are ‘moot’ in the sense that there is simply nothing to settle them. Defenders of the ‘easy approach’ to ontology, by contrast, think not that these questions are unsettled, but that they are very easily settled by trivial inferences from uncontroversial premises—so obviously and easily settled that there is no point debating them. The views may differ in terms of how far the deflation extends—while easy ontology deflates debates about ordinary objects, Yablo doesn’t think his view does. But the crucial underlying difference lies in whether we think there are ontological presuppositions for introducing terminology.
346. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 9/10
C. S. I. Jenkins Serious Verbal Disputes: Ontology, Metaontology, and Analyticity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper builds on some important recent work by Amie Thomasson, wherein she argues that recent disputes about the existence of ordinary objects have arisen due to eliminiativist metaphysicians’ misunderstandings. Some, she argues, are mistaken about how the language of quantification works, while others neglect the existence and significance of certain analytic entailments. Thomasson claims that once these misunderstandings are cleared away, it is trivially easy to answer existence questions about ordinary objects using everyday empirical methods of investigation. She reveals how two conflicting metaontologies can lead to different positions in the first-order debate. In this paper, I bring a third metaontological perspective to the table: one that enables us to maintain that ontological disputes about ordinary objects are not trivially easy to settle, even if we agree with Thomasson that they are merely verbal. These are serious verbal disputes.
347. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 9/10
Kristie Lyn Miller Defending Substantivism about Disputes in the Metaphysics of Composition
348. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 9/10
Stephen Yablo Carnap’s Paradox and Easy Ontology
349. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 111 > Issue: 9/10
Shamik Dasgupta The Possibility of Physicalism
350. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 1
Chrisoula Andreou Parity, Comparability, and Choice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is often supposed that, given two potential objects of choice X and Y, a specific set of circumstances, and a specific choosing agent, one of the following must be true: (1) opting for X is a better choice than opting for Y, (2) opting for Y is a better choice than opting for X, or (3) opting for X and opting for Y are exactly equally good choices. My aim in this paper is to show how some philosophical insights concerning color perception can illuminate the possibility of two options, X and Y, being such that, even given a specific set of circumstances and a specific choosing agent, none of (1), (2), or (3) holds, but X and Y are positively related to one another as “on a par.”
351. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 1
Alan Carter A Solution to the Purported Non-Transitivity of Normative Evaluation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Derek Parfit presents his Mere Addition Paradox in order to demonstrate that it is extremely difficult to avoid the Repugnant Conclusion. And in order to avoid it, Parfit has embraced perfectionism. However, Stuart Rachels and Larry Temkin, taking their lead from Parfit, have concluded, instead, that the Repugnant Conclusion can be avoided by denying the axiom of transitivity with respect to the all-things-considered-better-than relation. But this seems to present a major challenge to how we evaluate normatively. In this article I show how the Mere Addition Paradox and the Repugnant Conclusion can both be avoided without subscribing to perfectionism, and without sacrificing the axiom of transitivity.
352. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 1
John N. Williams, Neil Sinhababu The Backward Clock, Truth-Tracking, and Safety
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
We present Backward Clock, an original counterexample to Robert Nozick’s truth-tracking analysis of propositional knowledge, which works differently from other putative counterexamples and avoids objections to which they are vulnerable. We then argue that four ways of analyzing knowledge in terms of safety, including Duncan Pritchard’s, cannot withstand Backward Clock either.
353. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 10
Nick Zangwill Logic as Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I defend logical realism. I begin by motivating the realist approach by underlining the difficulties for its main rival: inferentialism. I then focus on AND and OR, and delineate a realist view of these two logical constants. The realist view is developed in terms of Alexander’s Principleshowing that AND and OR have distinctive determining roles. After that, I say what logic is not. We should not take logic to be essentially about the mind, or language, or exclusively about an abstract realm, or about reasoning, truth, truth-tables, truth-functions, topic-neutrality or form. Lastly, I turn to consider NEGATION and argue that we cannot escape negative facts, and facts conjoining and disjoining negative facts with positive facts. I then give NEGATION a distinctive role, one that contrasts with AND and OR. I reflect on the notion of logic in the coda.
354. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 10
Casey O’Callaghan The Multisensory Character of Perception
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
My thesis is that perceptual awareness is richly multisensory. I argue for this conclusion on the grounds that certain forms of multisensory perceptual experience are incompatible with the claim that each aspect of a perceptual experience is associated with some specific sensory modality or another. First, I explicate what it is for some feature of a conscious perceptual episode to be modality specific. Then, I argue based on philosophical and experimental evidence that some novel intermodal features are perceptible only through the coordinated use of multiple senses. I appeal to cases that involve consciously perceptible feature instances and feature types that could not be perceptually experienced through the use of individual sense modalities working on their own or simply in parallel and co-consciously. Finally, I offer an account of how to type perceptual experiences by modality that makes room for richly multisensory experiences.
355. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 11
Juan Comesaña Normative Requirements and Contrary-to-Duty Obligations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I argue that normative requirements (like “If you believe that it is raining, you ought to believe that it is precipitating”) should be interpreted as the conditional obligations of dyadic deontic logic. Semantically, normative requirements are conditionals understood as restrictors, the prevailing view of conditionals in linguistics. This means that Modus Ponens is invalid, even when the premises are known.
356. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 11
Lina Jansson Explanatory Asymmetries: Laws of Nature Rehabilitated
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The problem of explanatory non-symmetries provides the strongest reason to abandon the view that laws can figure in explanations without causal underpinnings. I argue that this problem can be overcome. The solution that I propose starts from noticing the importance of conditions of application when laws do explanatory work, and I go on to develop a notion of nomological (non-causal) dependence that can tackle the non-symmetry problem. The strategy is to show how a strong notion of counterfactual dependence as guaranteed by the laws is a plausible account of what we aim towards when we give law-based explanations. The aim of this project is not to deny that causal relations can do explanatory work but to restore laws of nature as capable of being explanatory even in the absence of any knowledge of causal underpinnings.
357. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 12
Manolo Martínez Modalizing Mechanisms
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is widely held that it is unhelpful to model our epistemic access to modal facts on the basis of perception, and postulate the existence of a bodily mechanism attuned to modal features of the world. In this paper I defend modalizing mechanisms. I present and discuss a decision-theoretic model in which agents with severely limited cognitive abilities, at the end of an evolutionary process, have states which encode substantial information about the probabilities with which the outcomes of a certain Bernoulli process occur. Thus, in the model, a process driven by very simple, thoroughly naturalistic mechanisms eventuates in modal sensitivity.
358. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 12
Miriam Schoenfield Bridging Rationality and Accuracy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper is about the connection between rationality and accuracy. I show that one natural picture about how rationality and accuracy are connected emerges if we assume that rational agents are rationally omniscient (have credence 1 in all of the facts about rationality). I then develop an alternative picture that allows us to relax this assumption, in order to accommodate certain views about higher order evidence.
359. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 2
Stephan Leuenberger The Contingency of Contingency
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Where does the line between the possible and the impossible fall? One influential answer to this question is succinctly expressed by the thesis that there are no brute necessities. Typically, that thesis is taken to be non-contingent by its proponents. In this paper, I shall argue that if it is necessary, it is so brutely. From this, it follows that there could be brute necessities. But this has no tendency to show that there are any. On the resulting view, the world is full of contingency—but only contingently so.
360. The Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 112 > Issue: 2
Justin Bledin Modus Ponens Defended
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Is modus ponens valid for the indicative conditional? McGee [1985] famously presents several alleged counterexamples to this inference rule. More recently, Kolodny and MacFarlane [2010] and Willer [2010] argue that modus ponens is unreliable in certain hypothetical contexts. However, none of these attacks undermines an informational conception of logic on which modus ponens is valid.