Displaying: 281-300 of 807 documents

0.064 sec

281. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
SUMARIO DEL VOL. 20/ CONTENTS OF VOL. 20
282. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Christopher Gauker On the Evidence for Prelinguistic Concepts
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Language acquisition is often said to be a process of mapping words into pre-existing concepts. If that is right, then we ought to be able to obtain experimental evidence for the existence of concepts in prelinguistic children. One line of research that attempts to provide such evidence is the work of Paul Quinn, who claims that looking-time results show that four--month old infants form “category representations”. This paper argues that Quinn’s results have an alternative explanation. A distinction is drawn between conceptual thought and the perception of comparative similarity relations, and it is argued that Quinn’s results can be explained in terms of the latter rather than the former.
283. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Sumario Analitico / Summary
284. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Sumario del Vol. 19 / Contents of Vol. 19
285. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Sumario del Vol. 19 / Contents of Vol. 19
286. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Sumario del Vol. 19 / Contents of Vol. 19
287. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Indice de Autores / Author Index
288. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Francisco Rodríguez-Consuegra, Juan-José Acero-Fernández Presentation
289. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
John A. Lucy Through the Window of Language: Assessing the Influence of Language Diversity on Thought
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The way we understand language diversity, how languages differ in representing reality, affects our approach to understanding linguistic relativity, how that diversity affects thought. Historically, researchers divided over whether the diverse representations of reality across languages were natural or conventional, but all tacitly assumed an optimal fit between language and reality. Twenrieth century anthropological linguists interested in linguisric relativity have questioned this assumption and sought to characterize “reality” without it by using domain- or structure-centered approaches. Arguments are presented favoring structure-centered approaches, along with a case illustration. A concluding discussion emphasizes the broader significance of language diversity in human development.
290. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Charles Sayward Steiner versus Wittgenstein: Remarks on Differing Views of Mathematical Truth
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Mark Steiner criticizes some remarks Wittgenstein makes about Gödel. Steiner takes Wittgenstein to be disputing a mathematical result. The paper argues that Wittgenstein does no such thing. The contrast between the realist and the demonstrativist concerning mathematical truth is examined. Wittgenstein is held to side with neither camp. Rather, his point is that a realist argument is inconclusive.
291. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Andy Clark Word, Niche and Super-Niche: How Language Makes Minds Matter More
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
How does language (spoken or written) impact thought? One useful way to approach this important but elusive question may be to consider language itself as a cognition-enhancing animal-built structure. To take this perspective is to view language as a kind of self-constructed cognitive niche. These self-constructed cognitive niches play, I suggest, three distinct but deeply interlocking roles in human thought and reason. Working together, these three interlocking routines radically transform the human mind, and mark a genuine discontinuity in the space of anitnal minds.
292. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, William M. Fields, Pär Segerdahl, Duane Rumbaugh Culture Prefigures Cognition in Pan/Homo Bonobos
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article questions traditional experimental approaches to the study of primate cognition. Beecuse of a widespread assumption that cognition in non-human primates is genetically encoded and “natural,” these approaches neglect how profoundly apes’ cultural rearing experiences affect test results. We deseribe how three advanced cognitive abilities - imitation, theory of mind and language - emerged in bonobos maturing in a bi-species Pan/Homo culture, and how individual rearing differences led to individual forms of these abilities. These descriptions are taken from a rich ethnographic material, and we argue for the scientific superiority of participant-based ethnographic studies of primate cognition in shared Pan/Homo cultures.
293. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Craig Callender, Jonathan Cohen There Is No Special Problem About Scientific Representation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
We propose that scientific representation is a special case of a more general notion of representation, and that the relatively well worked-out and plausible theories of the latter are directly applicable to thc scientific special case. Construing scientific representation in this way makes the so-called “problem of scientific representation” look much less interesting than it has seerned to many, and suggests that some of the (hotly contested) debates in the literature are concerned with non-issues.
294. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Andreas Bartels Defending the Structural Concept of Representation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The aim of this paper is to defend the structural concept of representation, as defined by homomorphisms, against its main objections, namely: logical objections, the objection from misrepresentation, theobjection from failing necessity, and the copy theory objection. The logical objections can be met by reserving the relation ‘to be homomorphic to’ for the explication of potential representation (or, of the representational content). Actual reference objects (‘targets’) of representations are determined by (intentional or causal) representational mechanisms. Appealing to the independence of the dimensions of ‘content’ and ‘target’ also helps to see how the structural concept can cope with misrepresentation. Finally, I argue that homomorphic representations are not necessarily ‘copies’ of their representanda, and thus can convey scientific insight.
295. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
296. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
José Díez, Roman Frigg Introduction
297. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Pierre Cassou-Nogués Signs, figures and time: Cavaillès on “intuition” in mathematics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper is concerned with Cavaillès’ account of “intuition” in mathematics. Cavaillès starts from Kant’s theory of constructions in intuition and then relies on various remarks by Hilbert to apply it tomodern mathematics. In this context, “intuition” includes the drawing of geometrical figures, the use of algebraic or logical signs and the generation of numbers as, for example, described by Brouwer. Cavaillès argues that mathematical practice can indeed be described as “constructions in intuition” but that these constructions are not imbedded in the space and in the time of our Sensibility, as Kant bclieved: They take place in other structures which are engendered in the history of mathematics. This leads Cavaillès to a critical discussion of both Hilbert’s and Brouwer’s foundational programs.
298. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Roman Frigg Scientific Representation and the Semantic View of Theories
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is now part and parcel of the official philosophical wisdom that models are essential to the acquisition and organisation of scientific knowledge. It is also generally accepted that most models represent their target systems in one way or another. But what does it mean for a model to represent its target system? I begin by introducing three conundrums that a theory of scientific representation has to come to terms with and then address the question of whether the semantic view of theories, which is the currently most widely accepted account of theories and models, provides us with adequate answers to these questions. After having argued in some detail that it does not, I conclude by pointing out in what direction a tenable account of scientific representation might be sought.
299. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Sumario Analitico / Summary
300. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Sumario Analitico / Summary