Displaying: 301-320 of 807 documents

0.111 sec

301. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Mauricio Suárez, Albert Solé On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper we claim that the notion of cognitive representation (and scientific representation in particular) is irreducibly plural. By means of an analogy with the minimalist conception of truth, we show thatthis pluralism is compatible with a generally deflationary attitude towards representation. We then explore the extent and nature of representational pluralism by discussing the positive and negative analogies between the inferential conception of representation advocated by one of us and the minimalist conception of truth.
302. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Andoni Ibarra, Thomas Mormann Scientific Theories as Intervening Representations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper some classical representational ideas of Hertz and Duhem are used to show how the dichotomy between representation and intervention can be overcome. More precisely, scientific theories are reconstructed as complex networks of intervening representations (or representational interventions). The formal apparatus developed is applied to elucidate various theoretical and practical aspects of the in vivo/in vitro problem of biochemistry. Moreover, adjoint situations (Galois connections) are used to explain the relation berween empirical facts and theoretical laws in a new way.
303. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Robert G. Hudson The Relevance of History to Philosophy of Science
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
My task in this paper is to defend the legitimacy of historicist philosophy of science, defined as the philosophic study of science that takes seriously case studies drawn from the practice of science. Historicistphilosophy of science suffers from what I call the ’evidence problem’. The worry is that case studies cannot qualify as rigorous evidence for the adjudication of philosophic theories. I explore the reasons why one might deny to historical cases a probative value, then reply to these reasons on behalf of historicism. The main proponents of the view I am criticizing are Pitt (2001) and Rasmussen (2001).
304. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Murali Ramachandran How Believing Can Fail to Be Knowing
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper defends a simple, externalist account of knowledge, incorporating familiar conditions mentioned in the literature, and responds to Timothy Williamson’s charge that any such analysis is futile because knowledge is semantically un-analyzable. The response, in short, is that even though such an account may not offer a reductive analysis of knowledge-by way of more basic, non-circular concepts-it still has an explanatory advantage over Williamson’s own position: it explains how belief can fail to be knowledge.
305. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Olga Fernández Prat Particularity and Reflexivity in the Intentional Content of Perception
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A significant part of perception, especially in visual perception, is characterized by particularity (roughly, the view that in such cases the perceiver is aware of particular objects in the environment). The intuition of particularity, however, can be made precise in at least two ways. One way (proposed by Searle) is consistent with the view that the content of perception is to be thought of as existentially quantified. Another way (the “demonstrative element” view championed by Evans, Campbell and others in diverse ways) is not. This paper reconstructs the argumentative context in which these views are put forward, and, after mentioning some drawbacks of both views, as these have been advanced to date, suggests a new view that may be regarded as a compromise between the contenders.
306. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Jordi Fernández Memory and Perception: Remembering Snowflake
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
If I remember something, I tend to believe that I have perceived it. Similarly, if I remember something, I tend to believe that it happened in the past. My aim here is to propose a notion of mnemonic contentaccounts for these facts. Certain proposals build perceptual experiences into the content of memories. I argue that they Have trouble with the second belief. Other proposals build references to temporal locations into mnemonic content. I argue that they have trouble with the second one. I propose a notion of mnemonic Content that can account for the rationality of both beliefs.
307. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Sumario Analitico / Summary
308. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Sumario Analitico / Summary
309. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
310. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Manuel Liz Camouflaged Physical Objects: The Intentionality of Perception
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper is about perception and its objects. My aim is to suggest a new way to articulate some of the central ideas of direct realism. Sections 1 and 2 offer from different perspectives a panoramic view of the main problems and options in the philosophy of perception. Section 3 introduces the notion of “camouflage” as an interesting and promising alternative in order to explain the nature of the intentional objects of perception. Finally, section 4 makes use of this new notion in the analysis of the relationships between the intentionality of perception, the intentionality of thought, and the intentionality of language.
311. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Tobies Grimaltos, Carlos Moya Presentation
312. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 3
Dan López de Sa The Case against Evaluative Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I offer a characterization of evaluative realism, present the intuitive case against it, and offer two considerations to support it further: one concerning the internalist connection between values and motivation, and the other concerning the intuitive causal inefficacy of evaluative properties. The considerations ultimately rely on the former intuitions themselves, but are not devoid of interest, as they might make one revise what one took to be his own realistic supporting intuitions, if such one had.
313. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 3
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
314. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 3
SUMARIO DEL VOL. 21 / CONTENTS OF VOL. 21
315. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 21 > Issue: 3
Henrik Zinkernagel The Philosophy behind Quantum Gravity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper investigates some of the philosophical and conceptual issues raised by the search for a quantum theory of gravity. It is critically discussed whether such a theory is necessary in the first place, and how much would be accomplished if it is eventually constructed. I argue that the motivations behind, and expectations to, a theory of quantum gravity are entangled with central themes in the philosophy of science, in particular unification, reductionism, and the interpretation of quantum mechanics. I further argue that there are —contrary to claims made on behalf of string theory— no good reasons to think that a quantum theory of gravity, if constructed, will provide a theory of everything, that is, a fundamental theory from which all physics in principle can be derived.
316. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1
Josep E. Corbí The Mud of Experience and Kinds of Awareness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In Authority and Estrangement Richard Moran takes some rather illuminating steps towards getting rid of the Cartesian picture of self-knowledge. I argue, however, that Moran’s crucial distinction between deliberative and theoretical attitude is seriously contaminated by that traditional picture. More specifically, I will point out why some crucial aspects of the phenomena that Moran describes in terms of the interplay between the theoretical and the deliberative attitude, should rather be interpreted as a process that takes place within the deliberative attitude itself. The theoretical attitude will, as a result, constitute a rather marginal attitude towards one’s own psychological dispositions and experiences, the adoption of which only makes sense in rather peculiar, often pathological, situations.
317. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1
Richard Moran Replies to Critics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article, I respond to the comments of six philosophers on my book Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-knowledge. My reply to Josep Corbí mostly concerns the relation between the two modes of self-knowledge I call ‘avowal’ and ‘attribution’, and the sense of activity involved in self-knoweldge; in responding to Josep Prades I try to clarify my picture of deliberation and show that it is not ‘intellectualist’ in an objectionable sense; Komarine Romdenh-Romluc’s paper enables me to say some things about the idea of unconscious beliefs, specifically in relation to the phenomenological tradition; the paper by Hilan Bensusan and Manuel de Pinedo helps me to clarify my sense of the relation of the first-person perspective to the specifically normative relation to one’s beliefs and other attitudes; and Carla Bagnoli’s paper provides an opportunity to explore some connections between the deliberative stance and the notion of recognition in Hegel and in contemporary philosophy.
318. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1
Carla Bagnoli The Authority of Reflection
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines Moran’s argument for the special authority of the first-person, which revolves around the Self/Other asymmetry and grounds dichotomies such as the practical vs. theoretical, activity vs. passivity, and justificatory vs. explanatory reasons. These dichotomies qualify the self-reflective person as an agent, interested in justifying her actions from a deliberative stance. The Other is pictured as a spectator interested in explaining action from a theoretical stance. The self-reflective knower has authority over her own mental states, while the Spectator does not. I highlight the implications of this construal for a theory of action, and call attention onto some other interesting normative relations between the self-reflective agent and the Other that escape both the first-person and the third-person approach. My contention is that the authority of self-reflection (and of reason) is best understood as a relation of mutual recognition between self and others, hence from a second-person stance.
319. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1
Hilan Bensusan, Manuel de Pinedo When my Own Beliefs are not First-Personal Enough
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Richard Moran has argued, convincingly, in favour of the idea that there must be more than one path to access our own mental contents. The existence of those routes, one first-personal —through avowal— the other third-personal —no different to the one used to ascribe mental states to other people and to interpret their actions— is intimately connected to our capacity to respond to norms. Moran’s account allows for conflicts between first personal and third personal authorities over my own beliefs; this enable some instances of Moore-paradoxical cases to be meaningful. In this paper we reflect on the consequences of this view for the acquisition of beliefs, and argue that, as in the moral case, excessive concentration on a third-personal understanding of thought undermines the very idea of being directed to the world and of being capable to fully own our own beliefs. We suggest that maybe too much attention to epistemic virtues or to justification is misdirected and could produce beliefs that are themselves not first-personal enough.
320. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1
Komarine Romdenh-Romluc Suppressed Belief
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Moran conceives of conscious belief as a conscious activity, rather than awareness of a mental state. Once conscious belief is understood in this way, the notion of suppressed belief becomes problematic. In this paper, I draw on the work of Merleau-Ponty to sketch an account of suppressed belief. I suggest that suppressed beliefs should not be understood as attitudes towards propositions. Instead, they should be conceived as ways of perceiving and interacting with the world that are out of keeping with how one repre-sents it as being.