Displaying: 121-140 of 163 documents

0.115 sec

121. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Aurel David La documentation juridique
122. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Carlo Giacon Substance et essence chez Aristote
123. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Antonio Ibargüengoitia Problèmes rencontrés dans l'investigation de I'histoire de la philosophie au Mexique
124. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Léopold Flam La relation de Hegel et Marx, un problème d'actualité philosophique
125. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Hilmi-Ziya Ülken Relations et différences entre la connaissance et la valeur
126. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Izydora Dąmbska Les idées de Wittgenstein sur la non-contradiction et sur le caractère des propositions mathématiques
127. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
André Mercier Science et responsabilité
128. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Jaime Castañe Le primat du tout
129. Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie: Volume > 6
Philippe Devaux Philosophie et sciences
130. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 4 > Issue: 1
Dinu Moscal Logique et grammaire dans la définition du verbe copulatif
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Our objective in this paper is to clearly highlight the linguistic status of the copulative verb, especially with regard to the copula verb to be, with an eye on tracingthe influences of Logic on its approach as a syntactic entity and also on emphasizing the details that led to an eclectic definition. This epistemological approach aims at placing an emphasis on the subject of the diachronic and interdisciplinary copulative verb, in order to observe the way in which the conclusions from the level of the logical approach were transferred to the one of the linguistic approach and also to avoid the misuse of a series of concepts that were established either in a different domain or in the same domain, but at a different level. The main emphasis falls on defining the linguistic predicate through the grammatical tense.
131. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 5 > Issue: 3
Pierre Uzan Logique quantique et intrication
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Due to the failure of the classical principles of bivalence and verifunctionality, the logic of experimental propositions relative to quantum systemscannot be interpreted in Boolean algebras. However, we cannot say neither that this logic is captured by orthomodular lattices, as claimed by many authors along the line of Birkhoff‘s and von Neumann‘s standard approach. For the alleged violation of distributivity is based on the possibility of combining statements relative to complementary contexts, which does not refer to any experience and, consequently, has no meaning. Indeed, quantum logic should be interpreted in partial, transitive Boolean algebras whose compatibility relation limits the application of the connectives within each of its Boolean sub-algebras, which refer to partial, classical descriptions. Moreover, this approach of quantum logic makes it possible to deal with composite systems, which was not possible to do within the standard approach, and then to deal with the fundamental notion of quantum entanglement. The latter notion can be represented by a series of axioms of the object language that restrict the set of experimental statements bearing on a composite system, while its close link to the notion of complementarity can be expressed in the metalanguage.
132. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Luciano Boi Conception “dynamique” en géométrie, idéalisation et rôle de l’intuition
133. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 10 > Issue: 2
Philippe Besnard Systèmes d’inférence non monotone
134. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Jean-Pascal Alcantara La théorie leibnizienne du changement en 1676: une interpretation du dialogue Pacidius Philalethi a la lumière de la Caractéristique géométrique (Leibniz's Theory of Variation in 1676: an Interpretation of the Dialogue Pacidius Philalethi through the Characteristica geometrica)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Cherchant à refonder l’édifice euclidien, Leibniz a formulé une Caractéristique géométrique qui annonce les concepts géneraux de la théorie des ensembles. Dans ce cadre, il a pu en particulier formaliser sa conception du continu. L’intérêt du Pacidius Philalethi (1676) est de montrer qu’en choisissant la conception intensionnelle du continu -position qu’il ne dementira jamais- il sélectionne parmi les images duales celle dont se déduit le changement qualitatif, base d’une philosophie naturelle qui soutiendra encore la dynamique ultérieure. Une tâche se dessine maintenant, soit déduire la nécessité d’un mouvement universei et infiniment varié à partir de ses conditions topologiques.We know that Leibniz intended to bring new foundations to the euclidean geometry and he has according to this view formulate a Characteristica geometrica which announces few general concepts of set theory. Parlicularly he tried to formalise his conception of continuity. Before the main interest of the Pacidius Philalethi (1676) is here: showing us that Leibniz when he chooses an intensional conception of continuity he chooses in the same time the dual image from which be can deduce the qualitative variation. We reckon again these conception at the grounds of his later philosophy of nature. But now we have to follow Leibniz demostrating how universal and infinite variations flow from its topological conditions.
135. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Newton C.A. Da Costa, Jean-Yves Béziau Définition, Théorie des Objets et Paraconsistance (Definition, Objects’ Theory and Paraconsistance)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Trois sortes de définitions sont présentées et discutées: les définitions nominales, les définitions contextuelles et les définitions amplificatrices. On insiste sur le fait que I’elimination des definitions n’est pas forcement un procede automatique en particulier dans le cas de la logique paraconsistante. Finalement on s’int’resse à la théorie des objets de Meinong et l’on montre comment elle peut êrre considéréecomme une théorie des descripteurs.Three kinds of definitions are presented and discussed: nominal definitions, contextual definitions, amplifying definitions. It is emphasized that the elimination of definitions is not necessarily straightforward in particular in the case of paraconsistent logic. Finally we have a look at Meinong’s theory objects and we show how it can be considered as a theory of descriptors.
136. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
James Gasser Colloque Lesniewski
137. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Georges Kalinowski Sur le fondement des normes et des énoncés normatifs: á propos des idées de von Wright et de Castañeda
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A dix ans d’intervalle deux déontciens de premier plan, G.H. von Wright et H.N. Castañeda, ont abordé -indépendamment l’un de l’autre- le probleme du fondement des normes et des énoncés normatifs. Leurs solutions respectives méritent d’être attentivement examinées. Ne prêtent-elles pas a discussion? Pour qu’une norme juridique soit fondée, suffit-il qu’elle soit édictée par un législateur compétent conformément a la procédure législative en vigueur? Un énoncé nornlatif est-il fondé du moment que l’ordre en faisant partie est légitimé au sens conféré a ce terme par l’auteur de Thinking and doing? Et tout d’abord peut-on admettre que les ordres fassent partie des énoncés nomlatifs? L’article qui suit essaie de répondre à ces questions et aux questions connexes.
138. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 1 > Issue: 3
Jean-Blaise Grize Preuves et raisons
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper everyday reasoning is examined fromm the standpoint of natural logic. In natural logic there is the supposition of the concept of schematisation, i.e. the discursive representation of a situation that a speaker A constructs for a listener B and that B must reconstruct for himself.Under these circumstances, in order to prove that a statement s is true A must present it in such a way that B does not call it into question, that he considers it a fact. For this it is necessary to have proofs. Moreover, a fact is never isolated and it may therefore appear inconsistent with other facts. A is thus led to provide reasons in order to substantiate his statements.Some mechanisms of proofs and of reasons are investigated.
139. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 1 > Issue: 3
Colloque international “L’ambiguïté et la paraphrase”
140. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 1 > Issue: 3
Miguel Sánchez-Mazas Le programme “Ars judicandi”