Displaying: 341-360 of 539 documents

0.142 sec

341. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Stevens F. Wandmacher The Bright Line of Ethical Agency
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his article The Nature, Importance, and Difficulty of Machine Ethics, James H. Moor distinguishes two lines of argument for those who wish to draw a “bright line” between full ethical agents, such as human beings, and “weaker” ethical agents, such as machines whose actions have significant moral ramifications. The first line of argument is that only full ethical agents are agents at all. The second is that no machine could have the presumed features necessary for ethical agency. This paper shows why Moor is mistaken in his refutation of the first line of argument; it also makes a positive case that “weaker” ethical agents are not agents at all. This positive case, however, allows Moor’s rejection of the second line of argument to stand: allowing that there could be moral machines, but that these machines would have to be full moral agents and not merely something that models moral behavior or can be used in morally charged ways.
342. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Christine Boshuijzen-van Burken Beyond Technological Mediation: A Normative Practice Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Several philosophers of technology have argued that technology mediates human actions. For example, in the branch of post-phenomenology, authors such as Don Ihde and Peter-Paul Verbeek have described the mediating aspects of technology in terms of morality of technology (more prominent in Verbeek) as well as in the sense that technology changes our perception of ourselves and the world (more prominent in Ihde). In this article, different existing types of mediation are presented, critiqued, and enriched. The four types are illustrated by referring to military high-tech environments with a focus on visual data and imaging technologies. These technologies can mediate actions (1) by inviting certain behavior, (2) through amplification and reduction, (3) through built-in norms, and (4) through interpretation. The four types of mediation mainly focus on the technology or technological artifact itself. What these approaches fail to grasp, however, is the specific user practices in which most technologies function. In this article, it is argued that to understand the mediating aspects of technology more fully, attention should be paid to the specific user context in which the technology functions. Therefore, an enriched understanding of the four types of mediation of technology is proposed by taking the lens of normative practices and analyzing the different types of mediation through this lens. The Kunduz airstrike incident, which took place in 2009 in Afghanistan, is a case in which a visual data sharing device called Rover played a prominent role. This case is used in this article to illustrate how technology mediates human actions in military practice.
343. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Chrysanthos Voutounos, Andreas Lanitis A Cultural Semiotic Aesthetic Approach for a Virtual Heritage Project: Part A—The Semiotic Foundations of the Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper presents an integrated framework applied towards the design and evaluation of a virtual museum of Byzantine art that combines the theorized fields of semiotics, virtual heritage (VH), and Byzantine art. A devised semiotic model, the case study semiosphere, synthesizes important principles from the theoretical background justifying the overall design and evaluation methodology. The approach presented has theoretical extensions to the understanding of the role technology plays in promoting a consummatory aesthetic experience for Byzantine art in virtual environments, complementing the experience received from traditional Byzantine art media. Part A of the work presents the development of the semiotic foundation of the study prior to presenting the applied potential of the approach in design and evaluation of VH for Byzantine art, which appears in Part B. The final task of the proposed approach aims to support a meaningful interpretation, assisting in the promotion of the significance (value) of the virtual museum to potential interpreters/visitors.
344. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Kristin Shrader-Frechette Reductionist Philosophy of Technology: Stones Thrown from Inside a Glass House
345. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Joseph C. Pitt The Author Replies
346. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Douglas Allchin Thinking about Technology and the Technology of "Thinking about"
347. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Davis Baird Organic Necessity: Thinking about Thinking about Technology
348. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Paul B. Thompson Thinking About Thinking About Technology
349. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Paul T. Durbin Guest Editor’s Introduction
350. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Keekok Lee Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration
351. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Syed Mustafa Ali Too Far, Yet Not Far Enough: A Heideggerian Response To Héctor José Huyke's Technologies And The Devaluation Of What Is Near.
352. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Paul T. Durbin Activist Philosophy of Technology and the Preservation of Biodiversity
353. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Marc J. de Vries The Nature of Technological Knowledge: Extending Empirically Informed Studies into What Engineers Know
354. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Jim Wishloff Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Reply to Lee
355. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Peter Kroes Screwdriver Philosophy; Searle's analysis of technical functions
356. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 3
Hé José Huyke Technologies and the Devaluation of What is Near
357. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Jeroen De Ridder The (Alleged) Inherent Normativity of Technological Explanations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Technical artifacts have the capacity to fulfill their function in virtue of their physicochemical make-up. An explanation that purports to explicate this relation between artifact function and structure can be called a technological explanation. It might be argued, and Peter Kroes has in fact done so, that there issomething peculiar about technological explanations in that they are intrinsically normative in some sense. Since the notion of artifact function is a normative one (if an artifact has a proper function, it ought to behave in specific ways) an explanation of an artifact’s function must inherit this normativity.In this paper I will resist this conclusion by outlining and defending a ‘buck-passing account’ of the normativity of technological explanations. I will first argue that it is important to distinguish properly between (1) a theory of function ascriptions and (2) an explanation of how a function is realized. The task of the former is to spell out the conditions under which one is justified in ascribing a function to an artifact; the latter should show how the physicochemical make-up of an artifact enables it to fulfill its function. Second, I wish to maintain that a good theory of function ascriptions should account for the normativity of these ascriptions. Provided such a function theory can be formulated — as I think it can — a technological explanation may pass the normativity buck to it. Third, to flesh out these abstract claims, I show how a particular function theory — to wit, the ICE theory by Pieter Vermaas and Wybo Houkes — can be dovetailed smoothly with my own thoughts on technological explanation.
358. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Carl Mitcham In Qualified Praise of the Leon Kass Council On Bioethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper argues the distinctiveness of the President’s Council on Bioethics, as chaired by Leon Kass. The argument proceeds by seeking to place the Council in proper historical and philosophical perspective and considering the implications of some of its work. Sections one and two provide simplified descriptions of the historical background against which the Council emerged and the character of the Council itself, respectively. Section three then considers three basic issues raised by the work of the Council that are of relevance to philosophy and technology as a whole: the role of professionalism, the relation between piecemeal and holistic analyses of technology, and the appeal to human nature as a norm.
359. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Lotte Asveld Informed Consent in the Fields of Medical Technological Practice.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Technological developments often bring about new risks. Informed consent has been proposed as a means to legitimize the imposition of technological risks. This principle was first introduced in medical practice to assure the autonomy of the patient.The introduction of IC in the field of technological practice raises questions about the comparability of the type of informed consent. To what extent are thepossibilities to include laypeople in making decisions regarding risks similar in the technological field to giving informed consent in the medical field and whatdoes this imply for the design and implementation of IC in the technological field? Medical and the technological practice are clearly alike in that both fieldsare characterized by highly specialized, technical knowledge which can be quite inaccessible to the average layperson. However, a fundamental difference ariseswith regard to the aim, knowledge of risks and exclusiveness of the practices in each field. The differences in aim imply that the necessity for each practice isperceived differently by laypeople, thus leading them to assess the respective risks differently. The differences in knowledge of risks arise from the variabilityin the ways that can be used to describe a given risk. Definition of risk in medical practice is more homogenous in this respect than the risk definition intechnological fields. Futhermore, medical practice tends to be more exclusive, leading laypeople immersed in that practice to necessarily embrace most of thefundamental underlying that practice. These differences result in divergent recommendations for the implementation of informed consent in the technological field, basically: there is a need for more extensive procedure and for less decisive authority for the individual.
360. Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Sven Ove Hansson Safe Design
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Safety is an essential ethical requirement in engineering design. Strategies for safe design are used not only to reduce estimated probabilities of injuries but also to cope with hazards and eventualities that cannot be assigned meaningful probabilities. The notion of safe design has important ethical dimensions, such as that of determining the responsibility that a designer has for future uses (and misuses) of the designed object.