Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 341-360 of 1835 documents

0.091 sec

341. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
David C. Williams Natural and Divine Law: Reclaiming the Tradition for Christian Ethics
342. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Michael Bergmann Agent Causation and Responsibility: A Reply to Flint
343. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Kai-man Kwan Is the Critical Trust Approach to Religious Experience Incompatible with Religious Particularism?: A Reply to Michael Martin and John Hick
344. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Mark C. Murphy Pro-Choice and Presumption: A Reply to Kenneth Einar Himma
345. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Kevin Corcoran Material Persons, Immaterial Souls and an Ethic of Life
346. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Peter C. Meilaender The Problem of Having Only One City: An Augustinian Response to Rawls
347. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Andrew Gustafson Utilitarians and Religion
348. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
J. R. Lucas God and Time: Essays on the Divine Nature
349. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Daniel Howard-Snyder In Defense of Naïve Universalism
350. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Katherin A. Rogers Does God Cause Sin?: Anselm of Canterbury Versus Jonathan Edwards on Human Freedom and Divine Sovereignty
351. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Michael J. Murray Natural Providence (Or Design Trouble)
352. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Robert Sloan Lee Hume's Abject Failure: The Argument Against Miracles
353. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Merold Westphal The God Who Will Be: Hermeneutics and the God of Promise
354. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Hugo A. Meynell The Philosophy of Dooyeweerd: A Transcendental Thomist Appraisal
355. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
J. William Forgie The Alleged Dependency of the Cosmological Argument on the Ontological
356. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Wes Morriston Must Metaphysical Time Have a Beginning?
357. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 4
Robert McKim Paul Griffiths: PROBLEMS OF RELIGIOUS DIVERSITY
358. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 4
Patricia Altenbernd Johnson Sarah Coakley: POWERS AND SUBMISSIONS
359. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 4
Lynne Rudder Baker WHY CHRISTIANS SHOULD NOT BE LIBERTARIANS: AN AUGUSTINIAN CHALLENGE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The prevailing view of Christian philosophers today seems to be that Christianity requires a libertarian conception of free will. Focusing on Augustine’s mature anti-Pelagian works, I try to show that the prevailing view is in error. Specifically, I want to show that---on Augustine’s view of grace-a libertarian account of free will is irrelevant to salvation. On Augustine’s view, the grace of God through Christ is sufficient as weIl as necessary for salvation. Salvation is entirely in the hands of God, totally independent of anything that any human being might do. And faith, the human response to salvation, is best understood in terms of a compatibilist account of freedom.
360. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 4
Scott MacDonald PETIT LARCENY, THE BEGINNING OF ALL SIN: AUGUSTINE’S THEFT OF THE PEARS
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his reflections on his adolescent theft of a neighbor’s pears, Augustine first claims that he did it just because it was wicked. But he then worries that there is something unacceptable in that claim. Some readers have found in this account Augustine’s rejection of the principle that all voluntary action is done for the sake of some perceived good. I argue that Augustine intends his case to call the principle into question, but that he does not ultimately reject it. His careful and resourceful analysis of the motivations of his theft adds subtlety to his own understanding of voluntary action and allows hirn to introduce an important component of his general account of sin, namely, that it essentially involves prideful self-assertion in imitation of God.