Displaying: 301-320 of 1519 documents

0.107 sec

301. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
In Memoriam
302. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Olivier Reboul Nietzsche's Critique of Kant
303. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Volker Gerhardt The Concept of Life in Kant and Nietzsche
304. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Joshua Rayman Nietzsche's Temporal Critiques of Kantian Universality
305. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Martin Schönfeld The Thing-in-itself in Nietzsche and Kant: Analysis of a Misunderstanding
306. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Eric Dufour The Determination of Action: Nietzsche's Critique of Kant
307. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Evaldo Sampaio Theory of Knowledge in an Extra-Moral Sense
308. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
R. Kevin Hill Nietzsche's Critique of Metaphysics
309. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Andrea Rehberg Nietzsche Beyond Kant: From Critique to Physiological Thinking
310. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Maurizio Ferraris Silvaplana, 14 August 1881: Eternal Recurrence
311. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Helmut Heit On Nietzsche and the Sciences I and II: Programmatic Concerns after Babich and Cohen
312. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Peter Durno Murray Adrian Del Caro, Grounding the Nietzsche Rhetoric of the Earth
313. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Nicholas Birns Horst Hutter and Eli Friedland, eds. Nietzsche's Therapeutic Teaching: For Individuals and Culture
314. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Simon Rogghe Olivier Ponton, Nietzsche - Philosophie de la légèreté
315. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Gregory Canning Antoine Panaïoti, Nietzsche and Buddhist Philosophy
316. New Nietzsche Studies: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1/2
Notes on Contributors
317. Fichte-Studien: Volume > 45
Douglas Moggach Contextualising Fichte: Leibniz, Kant, and Perfectionist Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
An examination of the intellectual context in which Fichte develops his ethical program in the Jena period and its immediate aftermath (1794–1800) reveals the determining presence of Leibniz, and the complex heritage of Leibnizian perfectionist thought from which Kantian, and post-Kantian, ethics seek to extricate themselves. While Kant blocks any reversion to the older, Leibnizian perfectionism, his criticisms leave open a space for a new kind of perfectionist ethic, one whose object is the promotion not of any determinate notion of eudaimonia or thriving, but of the possibility of free agency itself. The aim of post-Kantian perfectionism is to sustain the conditions of free, spontaneous action. Fichte’s ethical system is one example of post-Kantian perfectionism.
318. Fichte-Studien: Volume > 45
Daniel Breazeale In Defense of Conscience: Fichte vs. Hegel
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
First in the Phenomenology and then in the Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Hegel rejects Fichte’s notion of conscience on the grounds that it leads to despair (since the agent can never be sufficiently well-informed to know that he is doing the “right” thing). He also criticizes Fichtean conscience as purely “formal” and “abstract” and compatible with any content, which it can obtain only arbitrarily from the manifold of one’s natural drives and inclinations. For Hegel, there is an unresolvable tension between the claimed “universality” of a conscientious deed and the natural particularity of every moral agent, which ultimately leads to ethical egoism and hypocrisy. The aim of this paper is to show, first, that Hegel misrepresents key aspects of Fichte’s position and, second, that Fichte possesses the resources to respond successfully to most of Hegel’s criticisms. In order to grasp this one must closely examine Fichte’s subtle and often misunderstand account of moral deliberation and conscientious decision-making and the relation of the same to his larger account of I-hood.
319. Fichte-Studien: Volume > 45
Frederick Beiser Neo-Kantianism as Neo-Fichteanism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article defends the paradoxical thesis that neo-Kantianism is better described as neo-Fichteanism rather than neo-Kantianism. It maintains that neo-Kantianism is closer to Fichte than Kant in four fundamental respects: in its nationalism, socialism, activism, and in its dynamic and quantitative conception of the dualism between understanding and sensibility. By contrast, Kant’s philosophy was cosmopolitan, liberal, non-activist quietist and held a static and qualitative view of the dualism between understanding and sensibility. I attempt to explain why it took the neo-Kantians so long to recognize these profound affinities with Fichte: they were influenced by Fries conception of Fichte as a speculative metaphysician. I argue that the hold of Friesian interpretation of Fichte was first broken by Emil Lask in his Fichtes Idealismus und die Geschichte.
320. Fichte-Studien: Volume > 46
Luis Fellipe Garcia Knowing, Creating and Teaching: Fichte’s Conception of Philosophy as Wissenschaftslehre
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Independently of the discussions on the development of Fichte’s philosophy, there is something that does not seem to change throughout the more than a dozen presentations of his doctrine, namely, his constant concern with the meaning of philosophy. This concern is such a structuring one for Fichte that he even decides to replace the very name of “philosophy” by another one, less heavy in meaning and better suited to elucidate the nature of this particular activity that constitutes his own project. He calls it the Wissenschaftslehre. In this term created by Fichte three verbs can be found: wissen (to know), schaffen (to create) and lehren (to teach) – we would like to propose that Fichte’s conception of philosophy can be brought out as the orchestrated action of those three activities: knowing, creating and teaching. The point here being not to say that Fichte had the idea in mind of composing these three verbs (wissen, schaffen, lehren) when he created the term Wissenschaftslehre, but only that those terms offer useful landmarks for the exploration of Fichte’s philosophical landscape.Unabhängig von den Diskussionen über die Entwicklung der Philosophie Fichtes gibt es etwas, das sich in den zahlreichen Darstellungen seiner Lehre nicht zu ändern scheint, nämlich seine ständige Auseinandersetzung mit der Bedeutung der Philosophie selbst. Diese Sorge ist für Fichte so entscheidend, dass er sogar beschließt, den Namen Philosophie durch einen anderen zu ersetzen, weniger schwer in der Bedeutung und nach ihm besser geeignet, das Wesen dieser besonderen Tätigkeit, die sein eigenes Projekt zum Ausdruck bringt, aufzuklären. Er nennt es die „Wissenschaftslehre“. In diesem von Fichte geschaffenen Begriff lassen sich drei Verben auffinden: Wissen, Schaffen und Lehren. Im vorliegenden Aufsatz möchte ich vorschlagen, dass Fichtes Auffassung von Philosophie als die orchestrierte Handlung dieser drei Tätigkeiten angesehen werden kann: Wissen, Schaffen und Lehren. Ich will damit nicht behaupten, dass Fichte die explizierte Absicht hatte, diese drei Verben zu komponieren als er den Begriff „Wissenschaftslehre“ schuf, sondern nur, dass diese Begriffe nützliche Anhaltspunkte für die Erforschung von Fichtes philosophischer Landschaft anbieten.