Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 61-80 of 85 documents

0.061 sec

61. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 26
News and Announcements
62. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 26
Recent Works on Berkeley (2010 – 2017)
63. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 26
Daniel Carey, Marc A. Hight Conference Report: Bishop Berkeley’s Querist in Context
64. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 27
Marta Szymańska-Lewoszewska Unity, Diversity, and Order: National Religion in Berkeley’s Works 1735-1752
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The article discusses Berkeley’s idea of how to promote the common good in Ireland in the first half of the 18th century when society differed in respect to religion, political obedience, language, and culture. More specifically, since religion was still the core of Berkeley’s vision of human well-being, the article contains a reconstruction of his views on religious diversity and tolerance, as they were discussed in his works published between the 1730s and 1750s, when he was Bishop in Cloyne and published his most practical works. They will be analyzed in order to present the meaning of an evolution in his attitude towards Irish Catholics during the period. My particular aim is to show that the ‘Good Bishop’ sincerely aimed at the conversion of their hearts to the ‘true religion’, despite his officially moderate attitude towards them after the Jacobite Rebellion of 1745.
65. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 27
Recent Works on Berkeley (2010 – 2017)
66. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 27
News and Announcements
67. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 28
Recent Works on Berkeley (2017 – 2019)
68. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 28
News and Announcements
69. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 28
Jessica Gordon-Roth Tracing Reid’s ‘Brave Officer’ Objection Back to Berkeley—And Beyond
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Berkeley’s two most obvious targets in Alciphron are Shaftesbury and Mandeville. However, as numerous commentators have pointed out, there is good reason to think Berkeley additionally targets Anthony Collins in this dialogue. In this paper, I bolster David Berman’s claim that “Collins looms large in the background” of Dialogue VII, and put some meat on the bones of Raymond Martin and John Barresi’s passing suggestion that there is a connection between the Clarke–Collins correspondence, Alciphron, and the objection that Berkeley raises regarding persons and their persistence conditions therein. Specifically, I argue that we have evidence that Berkeley’s objection to consciousness–based views of personal identity, as found in VII.8, is a response to a challenge that Collins raises to Clarke in “An Answer to Mr. Clarke’s Third Defense of his Letter to Mr. Dodwell.” This is significant not just because this objection is usually—and consistently—taken to be an objection to Locke, but also because Berkeley’s objection works against Collins’s theory of personal identity in a way that it doesn’t against Locke’s.
70. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 28
Daniel E. Flage Rickless and Passive Obedience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Samuel Rickless has recently defended an act utilitarian interpretation of Berkeley’s Passive Obedience. Part of his argument is a criticism of my natural law reading of Berkeley, particularly my contention that natural lawyers are committed to a distributive notion of universality, while utilitarians are committed to a collective sense of universality. This essay is, in part, a reply to Rickless’s criticisms. I argue that if we assume that Berkeley was either a natural lawyer or a utilitarian, and if we can find grounds for distinguishing natural law theories from utilitarian theories, then a natural law theory provides a more philosophically defensible fit with the texts than does a utilitarian theory.
71. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Manuel Fasko Review: Stephen H. Daniel. George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy
72. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Keota Fields Berkeley on the Meaning of General Terms
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I argue that for Berkeley the meaning of a general term is constituted by the multiple particular ideas indifferently signified by that term. This reading faces two challenges. First, Berkeley argues that the meaning of sentences containing general terms is constituted by the one idea signified by the name in that sentence rather than by multiple ideas, implying that general terms are meaningful although they do not signify multiple ideas. Second, Berkeley writes that finite minds know the meaning of the biblical phrase ‘good thing’ even though that phrase fails to signify any ideas at all. Both challenges are met by deploying Berkeley’s account of mediate perception.
73. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Manuel Fasko The Retrieval of the Letter ‘To the Author of the Minute Philosopher’ from September 9th, 1732: A Note
74. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Todd DeRose “Experience Itself Must Be Taught to Read and Write”: Scientific Practice and Berkeley’s Language of Nature
75. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Recent Works on Berkeley (2018 – 2021)
76. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
News and Announcements
77. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 29
Artem Besedin Review: Tom Jones. George Berkeley: A Philosophical Life
78. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 30
Peter West Getting Beyond “The Curtain of the Fancy:” Anti-Representationalism in Berkeley and Sergeant
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper argues for a re-evaluation of the relationship between Berkeley and his predecessor, the neo-Aristotelian thinker John Sergeant. In the literature to date, the relationship between these two thinkers has received attention for two reasons. First, some commentators have attempted to establish a causal connection between them by focusing on the fact that both thinkers develop a theory of “notions.” Second, some have argued that both Berkeley and Sergeant develop “anti-representationalist” arguments against Locke’s epistemology. The first issue has received much greater attention, particularly from commentators seeking an explanation for Berkeley’s use of the term “notion.” Only one scholar (G. A. Johnston in 1923) has considered Berkeley and Sergeant’s anti-representationalism in any depth. In this paper, I argue that the weight given to the causal connection between Berkeley and Sergeant’s “notions” is misplaced since the evidence in favor of this connection is weaker than is usually acknowledged. Instead, I build on Johnston’s analysis of the conceptual connection between Berkeley and Sergeant’s anti-representationalism. I first corroborate Johnston’s claim that there are striking similarities between their criticisms of Locke before going beyond that analysis to identify two important similarities between their anti-representationalist arguments.
79. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 30
Dávid Bartha Review: James Hill. The Notions of George Berkeley: Self, Substance, Unity and Power
80. Berkeley Studies: Volume > 30
Keota Fields Review: David Berman. The Essential Berkeley and Neo-Berkeley