Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 361-380 of 1143 documents

0.101 sec

361. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 4
John Beaudoin SOBER ON INTELLIGENT DESIGN THEORY AND THE INTELLIGENT DESIGNER
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Intelligent design theorists claim that their theory is neutral as to the identity of the intelligent designer, even with respect to whether it is a natural or a supernatural agent. In a recent issue of Faith and Philosophy, Elliott Sober has argued that in fact the theory is not neutral on this issue, and that it entails theexistence of a supernatural designer. I examine Sober’s argument and identify several hurdles it must overcome.
362. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Ian Wilks SKEPTICAL THEISM AND EMPIRICAL UNFALSIFIABILITY
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Arguments strong enough to justify skeptical theism will be strong enough to justify the position that every claim about God is empirically unfalsifiable. This fact is problematic because that position licenses further arguments which are clearly unreasonable, but which the skeptical theist cannot consistently accept as such. Avoiding this result while still achieving the theoretical objectives looked for in skeptical theism appears to demand an impossibly nuanced position.
363. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Justin P. McBrayer CORNEA AND INDUCTIVE EVIDENCE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One of the primary tools in the theist’s defense against “noseeum” arguments from evil is an epistemic principle concerning the Conditions Of ReasoNableEpistemic Access (CORNEA) which places an important restriction on what counts as evidence. However, CORNEA is false because it places too strong acondition on what counts as inductive evidence. If CORNEA is true, we lack evidence for a great many of our inductive beliefs. This is because CORNEA amounts to a sensitivity constraint on evidence, and inductive evidence is often insensitive. So unless a theist is also an inductive skeptic, she must abandon CORNEA in responding to this sort of argument from evil.
364. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Stephen R. Palmquist KANT’S RELIGIOUS ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD: THE ULTIMATE DEPENDENCE OF HUMAN DESTINY ON DIVINE ASSISTANCE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
After reviewing Kant’s well-known criticisms of the traditional proofs of God’s existence and his preferred moral argument, this paper presents a detailedanalysis of a densely-packed theistic argument in Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason. Humanity’s ultimate moral destiny can be fulfilled only through organized religion, for only by participating in a religious community (or “church”) can we overcome the evil in human nature. Yet we cannot conceive how such a community can even be founded without presupposing God’s existence. Viewing God as the internal moral lawgiver, empowering a community of believers, is Kant’s ultimate rationale for theistic belief.
365. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Daniel M. Johnson THE SENSE OF DEITY AND BEGGING THE QUESTION WITH ONTOLOGICAL AND COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Calvin famously interprets Romans 1 as ascribing human knowledge of God in nature not to inferences from created things (natural theology) but to a “senseof deity” that all people share and sinfully suppress. I want to suggest that the sense of deity interpretation actually provides the resources for explaining thepersuasive power and usefulness of natural theology. Specifi cally, I will argue that understanding certain ontological and cosmological arguments as dependenton the sense of deity preserves their ability to persuade while helping solve serious problems with the justifi cation of their premises. In the case of the ontological argument, this will provide a new response to the most serious objection that the argument faces, the charge that it begs the question.
366. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Erik J. Wielenberg In Defense of Non-Natural, Non-Theistic Moral Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Many believe that objective morality requires a theistic foundation. I maintain that there are sui generis objective ethical facts that do not reduce to naturalor supernatural facts. On my view, objective morality does not require an external foundation of any kind. After explaining my view, I defend it against a variety of objections posed by William Wainwright, William Lane Craig, and J. P. Moreland.
367. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Jack Mulder, Jr. KIERKEGAARD AND NATURAL REASON: A CATHOLIC ENCOUNTER
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I consider Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous attack on natural theology with respect to how it lines up with Catholic thought on that topic. I argue that Kierkegaard’s recently shown similarities to accounts of basic beliefs raise an interesting question when a Catholic hybrid of basic beliefs and natural theology, which I develop in the paper, is considered. Kierkegaard does not attack what we might call natural reason, or a natural awareness of God’s existence, only natural theology’s demonstrative capabilities, and his reasons for doing the latter, in our current epistemological climate, are shown to be mistaken.
368. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 3
Merold Westphal Inverted Intentionality: On Being Seen and Being Addressed
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Continental philosophy of religion often takes place within the horizons of phenomenology. A central theme of this tradition is the correlation, in one form or another, of intentional act (noesis) and intentional object (noema), the “object” as given to or taken by the subject. But in dialectical tension with this theme is the notion of inverted intentionality in which the arrows of meaning bestowing intentionality come toward the self rather than emanating from the self. This theme is developed by Sartre, Levinas, and Derrida, among others. Since each of these is in some fashion an atheist, it is surprising but important that their reflections on what it means to be seen or to be addressed keep turning toward the question of God. This suggests that the basic concept is important for the philosophy of religion, at least in monotheistic contexts.
369. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 3
Mark C. Murphy Not Penal Substitution but Vicarious Punishment
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The penal substitution account of the Atonement fails for conceptual reasons: punishment is expressive action, condemning the party punished, and so is not transferable from a guilty to an innocent party. But there is a relative to the penal substitution view, the vicarious punishment account, that is neither conceptually nor morally objectionable. On this view, the guilty person’s punishment consists in the suffering of an innocent to whom he or she bears a special relationship. Sinful humanity is punished through the inglorious death of Jesus Christ; ill-desert is thus requited, and an obstacle to unity with God is overcome.
370. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 3
John M. Connolly Eudaimonism, Teleology, and the Pursuit of Happiness: Meister Eckhart on “Living Without a Why”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Recent interest among both philosophers and the wider public in the tradition of virtue ethics often takes its inspiration from Aristotle or from Thomas Aquinas. In this essay I briefly outline the ethical approaches of these two towering figures, and then describe more fully the virtue ethics of Meister Eckhart, a medieval thinker who admired, though critically, both Aristotle and Aquinas. His related but distinctively original approach to the virtuous life is marked by a striking and seemingly paradoxical injunction to “live without why.”
371. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 3
Katherin Rogers Back to Eternalism: A Response to Leftow’s “Anselmian Presentism”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Against my interpretation, Brian Leftow argues that Anselm of Canterbury held a presentist theory of time, and that presentism can be reconciled with Anselm’s commitments concerning divine omnipotence and omniscience. I respond, focusing mainly on two issues. First, it is difficult to understand the presentist theory which Leftow attributes to Anselm. I articulate my puzzlement in a way that I hope moves the discussion forward. Second, Leftow’s examples to demonstrate that presentism can be reconciled with Anselm’s understanding of the divine nature assume a mode of divine knowing which is different from what Anselm proposes. I stand by my interpretation.
372. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 3
Brian Leftow Anselmian Presentism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I rebut four claims made in a recent article by Katherin Rogers. En route I discuss how a timeless God might perceive all of “tensed” time at once.
373. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Ira M. Schnall ANTHROPIC OBSERVATION SELECTION EFFECTS AND THE DESIGN ARGUMENT
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The Argument from Fine-Tuning, a relatively new version of the Design Argument, has given rise to an objection, based on what is known as the An­thropic Principle. It is alleged that the argument is fallacious in that it involves an observation selection effect—that given the existence of intelligent living observers, the observation that the universe is fine-tuned for the existence of intelligent life is not surprising. Many find this objection puzzling, or at least easily refutable. My main contribution to the discussion is to offer an analysis of what is wrong (and what is right) in the objection.
374. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
James K. A. Smith CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: PRESCRIPTIONS FOR A HEALTHY SUBDISCIPLINE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Over the past decade there has been a burgeoning of work in philosophy of religion that has drawn upon and been oriented by “continental” sources in philosophy—associated with figures such as Martin Heidegger, Jacques Derrida, Emmanuel Levinas, Jean-Luc Marion, Gilles Deleuze, and others. This is a significant development and one that should be welcomed by the community of Christian philosophers. However, in this dialogue piece I take stock of the field of “continental philosophy of religion” and suggest that the field is developing some un-healthy patterns and habits. The burden of the paper is to suggest a prescription for the future health of this important field by articulating six key practices that should characterize further scholarship in continental philosophy of religion.
375. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Timothy Pawl, Kevin Timpe Incompatibilism, Sin, and Free Will in Heaven
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The traditional view of heaven holds that the redeemed in heaven both have free will and are no longer capable of sinning. A number of philosophers have argued that the traditional view is problematic. How can someone be free and yet incapable of sinning? If the redeemed are kept from sinning, their wills must be reined in. And if their wills are reined in, it doesn’t seem right to say that they are free. Following James Sennett, we call this objection to the traditional view of heaven ‘the Problem of Heavenly Freedom’. In this paper, we discuss and criticize four attempts to respond to the Problem of Heavenly Freedom. We then offer our own response to this problem which both preserves the traditional view of heaven and avoids the objections which beset the other attempts.
376. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Alvin Plantinga IN MEMORIAM: WILLIAM P. ASTON
377. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Hugh J. McCann GOD, SIN, AND ROGERS ON ANSELM: A REPLY
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Based on views she draws from Anselm, Katherin Rogers mounts an extend­ed attack on my account of God’s relationship to human sin. Here I argue first that if Anselm’s view of the relationship in question is different from my own, then Rogers fails to locate any reason for thinking his account is correct. I argue further that Rogers fails to demonstrate her claim that my account of God’s relation to sin makes him a deceiver, that her criticisms of my theodicy of sin are misguided, and that she is mistaken in claiming a world in which God has full sovereignty over human willing is less safe for the repentant than I hold it to be.
378. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Bruce Ellis Benson A RESPONSE TO SMITH’S “CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: PRESCRIPTIONS FOR A HEALTHY SUBDISCIPLINE”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
All of us working in continental philosophy of religion can be grateful to James K. A. Smith for his call to consider which practices will best further the “health” of the burgeoning subdiscipline of continental philosophy of religion. Given that he offers his suggestions “in the spirit of ‘conversation starters,’” my response is designed to continue what I hope will be an ongoing conversation. With that goal in mind, I respond to Smith by considering not only the practicality of each suggestion but also whether adopting practices he suggests would actually improve the health of the subdiscipline.
379. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
Alexander R. Pruss ANOTHER STEP IN DIVINE COMMAND DIALECTICS
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Consider the following three-step dialectics. (1) Even if God (consistently) commanded torture of the innocent, it would still be wrong. Therefore Divine Command Metaethics (DCM) is false. (2) No: for it is impossible for God to command torture of the innocent. (3) Even if it is impossible, there is a non-trivially true per impossibile counterfactual that even if God (consistently) com­manded torture of the innocent, it would still be wrong, and this counterfac­tual is incompatible with DCM. I shall argue that the last step of this dialectics is flawed because it would rule out every substantive metaethical theory.
380. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 4
James K. A. Smith THE END OF ENCLAVES: A REPLY TO BENSON
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In reply to Benson’s response, I agree that we should be seeking the dissolution of all enclaves in philosophy of religion—whether continental or analytic. But I continue to suggest that continental philosophy of religion bears special burdens in this respect.