Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 281-300 of 1318 documents

0.077 sec

281. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Serguei L. Katrechko How is Metaphysics Possible: On the way to Transcendental Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The answer to the question “How is metaphysics possible?” can be obtained with the help of Kant’s transcendental method. Discussing the possibility of metaphysics, Kant distinguishes two modes of it: metaphysica naturalis and metaphysics as a science. Therefore, the possibility of metaphysics is divided into two sub-questions. Postulated by Kant, metaphysica naturalis, which underlies philosophy, associated with active “Kraft” of mind (imagination and understanding) and roots in metaphysics of the language connected with the sense of language (conceptual and categorial) and its formal–structural nature. Thereby the man is homo metaphysicus. Before discussing the possibility of a “scientific” metaphysics it is necessary to consider, first of all, that metaphysics per se consists of metaphysica generalis and metaphysica specialis, and secondly, the development of it includes three historical modes: antiquity meta-physics (ontology), meta-psychology (epistemology) of modern era, contemporary (post-Kantian) metaphysics. The possibility of metaphysica generalis (or transcendental ontology) is manifested by specific ontological (transcendental) predicates, i.e. categories in the Kantian sense, which exist in our language. The possibility of metaphysica specialis (or transcendental metaphysics) is manifested by impredicative wholeness, or encompassing totalities (comp. with the Encompassing (das Umgreifende of K. Jaspers), which determine the appropriate regional ontology (Husserl).
282. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Gal Yehezkel Fear of Death and the Metaphysics of Time
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Lucretius points out a puzzling asymmetry in our attitudes towards our prenatal non-existence and our post-mortem non-existence. Normally, we view birth as a happy occasion, and death as a sad event. Some philosophers argue that these asymmetry in our attitude is justified by the A-theory of Time, which reflects the common sense way of thinking about time, and so they discredit the B-theory of Time. In this paper I critically examine these claims and argue that this belief is false. Our attitude is neither justified nor discredited by anything which is in debate between the A-Theory and the B-theory of time. Thus the existence of this asymmetry does not favor one theory over the other, and the dispute between the two theories will have to be settled on other grounds.
283. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Tiancheng Wang On the Implementations of Traditional Metaphysics in China and the West
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Chinese metaphysics and Western metaphysics share common resources, which are theoretical understandings on the contradiction between finiteness and eternity embedded in human beings, and the human reflections on the nature of their life. Nevertheless, the two kinds of metaphysics differ from each other concerning their constructing modes in the following two aspects. First, as to the establishing mode, Chinese metaphysics is in the ascending way, which is from the ethical world to the field of metaphysics; while Western metaphysics in the descending way, which starts from ontology, and arrives at ethics. Second, as to the methods of transcending the finiteness of human life, or the methods leading to eternity, the Chinese way is inner, while the Western one transcendent. The unity of these two aspects constitutes the difference between the constructing mode of Chinese metaphysics and that of Western metaphysics.
284. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Naoaki Kitamura The Connection between Grounding and Truthmaking
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The purpose of this paper is to clarify the connection between two notions of growing interest in contemporary metaphysics – truthmaking and grounding. The former has provoked a great deal of controversy since the 1980s, whereas the latter has attracted serious attention only since the beginning of this century. Although the two notions are closely connected, only a few attempts have been made so far at clarifying that connection. The present paper is intended as an investigation of the connection on the basis of the appreciation of the core ideas of truthmaker theory. To begin with, two conceptions of the connection are distinguished, and the conception that truthmaking can be defined in terms of grounding is endorsed. Next, two ideas that form the core of truthmaker theory are delineated, and it is argued that the definition of truthmaking should be based on the idea that truthmakers are metaphysically fundamental entities. Finally, it is shown that a particular problem with grounding can be resolved by restricting a relevant logical principle for grounding, justified by the idea that truth is a derivative aspect of reality. The discussion reveals the significance of appreciating the core of truthmaker theory in developing a theory of grounding.
285. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Valtteri Arstila Apparent Motion and Ontology of Time
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Introspectively, it appears that we can have experiences as of temporally extended phenomena such as change, motion, and the passage of time. A central question in the ontology of time is whether we can make sense of these experiences without assuming that the passage of time is real. The antireductionist argument against such a possibility maintains that if there is no passage of time, but only static time slices, then our experiences as of arguably temporally extended phenomena cannot be explained. Consequently, insofar as we can have such experiences, reductionists need to show that these experiences are in fact realized by static means. By drawing from cognitive sciences, this is exactly what Laurie A. Paul recently aimed to show. I will argue that Paul’s argumentation fails on two grounds. First, even if her argument for accounting apparent motion by static means is successful, it does not apply to other experiences of temporal phenomena. Second, there are reasons to doubt that even apparent motion is represented by static means. Accordingly, the antireductionist argument remains to be addressed.
286. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Jerry Kapus Rationality and Free Will
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is evident that we identify problems and reason about and implement solutions. Doing this involves deliberation of choices. Doing this involves rationality and free will. However, determinism tells us that this is not the case and that free will is an illusion. I think that this is a mistake, but I also think that we do not have an adequate alternative for understanding rationality in the context of free, deliberative choice. In this short paper, I sketch some problems with the compatibility of rationality with determinism, but I also argue that we are no better off with understanding free will as a necessary condition for rational action.
287. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Ming-Fui Chai Rationality and Identity: It’s More Personal than You Think
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, I will show how the distinction between consciousness and self-consciousness can clarify Locke’s doctrine of personal identity in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding and help us to better respond to Reid’s “brave officer” objection in Inquiry and Essays. We will see how Reid has misunderstood Locke and made wrong assumptions that undermine the credibility of his objection. Firstly, Locke differentiates between the terms ‘man’ and ‘person’ but Reid uses them interchangeably in his criticism of Locke. Secondly, Reid thinks that consciousness is equivalent to memory and that Locke’s theory of personal identity will result in contradictory conclusions. On one hand, the general is not the same person as the child because he cannot remember what he did as a child. But on the other hand, transitivity means they are in fact the same person. Reid fails to realize that Locke is in fact talking about self-consciousness in his Essay and the difference between consciousness and self-consciousness is grounded on the difference between a non-rational being like an animal, which can only have identity, and rational beings like us, who have personal identity. Also, to say that memory is equivalent to self-consciousness is wrong because memory is only a subset of self-consciousness.
288. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Heesung Kim The Significance of Subjective Materialistic Thought in Kant’s Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Subjective materialism is a new worldview of the subject of self-awareness based on man-in-the world, and a methodology of man interconnecting the world. Subjective materialism is a logical result of development in western philosophy. This logic comes from the metaphysics of Graeco, while its thinking originates from Kantian philosophy. Kant’s philosophy has been occupying the most important position in the history of western philosophy. Of important significance in the history of philosophy is a fact implied by the Copernican Revolution in Kant’s philosophy, namely the indication of the possibility for subjective materialism. A particular transcendental epistemology and its point of view about man’s free nature led to today’s subjective materialism. Subjective materialism is a finalization of Kantian philosophy in a materialistic form.
289. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Gaetano Chiurazzi Kant’s Revolutionary Metaphysics as a New Policy of Reason
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Kant’s critical project has been understood as a description of the functioning of knowledge (Strawson). Such an understanding of the first Critique seems however limited, especially if we consider Kant’s frequent use of political analogies. These analogies suggest another reading in which Kant’s critical project emerges as an attempt to overcome a state of nature in reason (marked by unavoidable conflict) through the institution of a legal state in and by reason itself. Seen in this perspective, Kant’s critical metaphysics can be considered revolutionary, because it assumes the issues of the two revolutions of modernity, the political and the scientific one: from the former, Kant adopts the conviction that a conflict can be settled only through the separation and reciprocal limitation of powers, as theorized by Locke and Montesquieu - and thus neither by force nor by the establishment of an absolute power; from the latter, he acquires a model of proof, which is based, not on description, but on the elaboration of an explicative hypothesis (of a condition of possibility). The Critique of Pure Reason, then, is not a mere treatise of epistemology or of descriptive metaphysics, but the attempt of setting up a policy of reason at the service of peace and civil communal life.
290. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Satoshi Suganuma Toward the Absolute Ultimate End
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In general, the ultimate end is the end beyond which there can be no further end. However, almost all the ultimate ends considered so far— “a man’s ultimate end”, “humanity’s ultimate end”, “the ultimate end of the universe”, and so on—are relative, in that they can in fact have a further end. Additionally, many of the ideas are based on dubious presuppositions such as teleology. Can there, then, be a meaningful idea of the absolute ultimate end without dubious presuppositions, beyond which there can never be any further end? And if so, what will it be like? This paper, by raising such questions, suggests a possible study of the absolute ultimate end, which has never been attempted before, at least explicitly. At first, the classic ideas of the ultimate end (typically attributed to Aristotle and Aquinas) and modern criticisms of them (typically attributed to Anscombe and Geach) are surveyed; then, postulates for the concept of the absolute ultimate end are presented (in §1: Toward a concept of the absolute ultimate end). Next, a definition of the absolute ultimate end (hereafter AUE) is presented, and it is argued that the idea of AUE is not based on (at least clearly) dubious presuppositions, and that AUE is the strongest meaningful ultimate end. Further, it is suggested that a study of AUE would be highly metaphysical—or even mystical—in character (in §2: Toward a study of the absolute ultimate end). Lastly, the possible relationships between us human and AUE are suggested (in §3: Toward the absolute ultimate end as our ultimate end).
291. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Natalia Martishina Construction of Objects and Construction of Realities
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The essence of human activity is a permanent constructing of objects. It means a creation of artifacts that have an internal structure and a logic of operating. What is the difference between constructing of objects and constructing of new realities as a metaphysical process? We understand a reality as a localized area of being or a set of objects that exist in a certain way (social reality, virtual reality, etc.). The criterion for the existence of local autonomous reality is its having the characteristics of the system, and these characteristics ensure its functioning, at least in part, as self-based. From this point of view, the presence of a number of objects of a particular type is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for the emergence of a new reality. The formation of the connections between the objects that fix the logic of the system is more important. A certain amount of immanent links is required for the birth of a new reality. The trend of the links development consists of their coordination to the point of logical completeness. Reality is constructed when the links have become sufficiently developed for the internal determination of new events in the system and / or requests for the extension of objects with established parameters. This transition can be illustrated by means of the art practice: at a certain point in a creative act when developing a story line, characters and the story itself begin to go their own line (not defined by the initial creative idea). Thus, the constructing activity aimed at new reality creating has a certain optimum.
292. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Helena Yatsenko Thinking in the Metaphysical Categories
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The problem of legitimacy of metaphysical knowledge is examined in the paper in connection with the antimetaphysical fervor of philosophy of postmodern, tendencies to “escape from ontology”, and deep crisis of humanities. The conceptual analysis of fundamental grounds of traditional metaphysics is conducted as a method of localization and orientation in space. The metaphysical systems of separate historical epochs are based on certain spatial metaphors: circle, cross, system of co-ordinates, surface. As an alternative practices a deconstruction offers fundamental ontology of Martin Heidegger which is focused on time as organizing principle of the universe. There is a task to proof a necessity and productivity of metaphysics as sciences and as a method of cognition.
293. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Jimmy Alfonso Licon Properly Functioning Brains and Personal Identity: A Novel Argument for Neural Animalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Surely, I persist through time; thus, I must be identical to something that persists through time. But, what is identical to me, which persists through time? First, I argue that we should take reductive materialism and the Lockean view of personal identity seriously. But, these positions appear in tension. Second, I argue a plausible way to reconcile them is to embrace a novel kind of animalism that I call neural animalism. This says that I am identical to my properly functioning brain.
294. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Zhengyu Sun Philosophy’s Adventures as Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
As the theoretically human self-consciousness, Philosophy is a kind of metaphysics which represents the metaphysical nature of human beings in denying reality and achieving their ideals. The most fundamentally cultural connotation of Philosophy lies in some metaphysical adventures which are to establish the holy form and to dissolve the unholy forms by means of conceptual critique. However, the meta-metaphysics resulting from the metaphysical adventures is not the end of Philosophy which aims at abandoning representing human self-consciousness in a theoretic way, but a kind of self-consciousness in contemporary human beings which is dedicated to unmask human selfestrangement in the unholy forms. And the latter is represented in regarding Philosophy itself as the object of critique.
295. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 23
Harris Hatziioannou Conceivability and Knowledge of Metaphysical Modality
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I first examine and reject a prominent rationalist approach to knowledge of metaphysical modality, advocated by philosophers such as Yablo and Chalmers, who rely on the notion of conceivability to explain how we can achieve such knowledge. The focus of my criticism concerns a particular requirement of these accounts, namely that the content of modally reliable conceivability intuitions, which is in the first instance a simple imaginary situation, can be extended to completeness and thus considered to be verifiable by a range of possible worlds. I thus argue that the notions these philosophers employ cannot provide the criteria by which we could understand how such an operation could be understood in a purely epistemic way. This is because they rely on substantial metaphysical assumptions, for instance the assumption that all aspects of (actual as well as possible) reality can in principle be represented and grasped by the human mind as a unified whole. These assumptions render their notion of conceivability inadequate to be used as an epistemic guide to possibility. Finally, I outline the broad epistemological principles that pertain to a specific Kripkean understanding of metaphysical necessity that I favor (Edgington 2004), which construes it as a kind of natural necessity.
296. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 25
Simone Cheli Eastern and Western Paths in Understanding
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper is devoted to explore a basic concept of psychology and of all humankind: understanding. As people and as psychologists, we are continuously faced with the issue of attempting to understand: events, people, and meanings. In clinical practice, the word “understanding” is like a mantra: it is the main process in which therapist and patient are involved and plays a key role in therapeutic experience. To the extent that we are “able to understand”, we constantly create new, vital spaces and opportunities of construing and living. In this paper we will cautiously try to understand understanding by examining different philosophical traditions, in order to explore the different paths and enlarge the approach to this fascinating construct. This paper is based on the assumption that understanding is present in and actively shapes every human culture.
297. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 25
Nikolaos Erinakis Prolegomena to a Historical Condition for Authenticity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
To conclude that certain desires are authentic, because simply they are outcomes of the current beliefs and values of the individual, without examining in which way these were formed seems inadequate to provide the assurance of authenticity. This paper maintains that contemporary theories of autonomy, which also discuss authenticity, including the ones of Frankfurt and Dworkin based on identification, seem insufficient and a conception closer to Christman and Mele’s models, which are based on historical conditions, should be explored. However, in contrast to the latter, it is argued that we should not only trust rationality and reflective thinking in distinguishing which are the authentic desires, values and beliefs, but also other properties of ours like intuition, inclinations and drives. Furthermore, it is suggested that a broader understanding of the conception of the agent’s resistance is required. Therefore, the aim of this essay is to conduct an outline of a historical condition for authenticity which will be able to overcome the weaknesses of both the former and the latter conceptions mentioned. This condition should be externalist, anti-intellectualist, not necessarily rationalist and content neutral.
298. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 25
Marcia Homiak On Learning to be Virtuous
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
On a view derived from Plato and Aristotle, being virtuous involves entrenched, wide-ranging dispositions not only to reason and act, but also to respond and feel. Because affective responses are crucial to being virtuous, Plato and Aristotle thought that it made all the difference how we are brought up. For Aristotle, this is matter of habituation: we learn by doing. What is it that we do when we learn by doing? There is no specific act associated with any virtue, so the answer cannot be that we perform the same kind of action countless times. Moreover, being virtuous involves caring sufficiently about someone or something such that we want to be virtuous. These remarks suggest that habituation is not a straightforward matter. I argue that we become virtuous not by performing actions stereotypically associated with the virtues, but by engaging in activities that give rise to the right loves and attachments. These attachments are the psychological grounding of virtue; without them, having a virtuous character is not possible.
299. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 25
Elisa Aaltola Emotion, Empathy and Core Moral Agency
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
With the recent sentimentalism revival, both emotion and empathy have re-emerged as prominent contenders for the throne of moral agency. Particularly the emotive argument, according to which emotions are both the necessary and sufficient criterion for moral ability, has become increasingly popular. The emotive argument is supported by neurostudies and social psychology, which have manifested that the majority of moral decision-making appears to be rested on immediate intuition, and ultimately emotion. However, not all have been willing to accept emotion as the foundation of moral agency, and particularly supporters of the rationalistic argument have presented an arsenal of criticisms against it. The paper explores this rift between Humean and Kantian ethics in the light of contemporary literature, and analyses particularly arguments offered by Jesse Prinz and Jeannette Kennett. It will be suggested that both emotion and reason fail to offer a convincing basis for moral agency, and that we should instead favour a multi-tier approach, with affective empathy as the key capacity on which core moral agency is built.
300. Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy: Volume > 25
Leah Bradshaw Have we Become Better?: A Commentary and Critique on Steven Pinker: The Better Angels of Our Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Paper examines Steven Pinker’s thesis that we have become ‘better angels’ throughout the course of Western history. Pinker’s markers for this improvement are secularity, science, cosmopolitanism, feminization and rational legal norms. Author argues that while some of Pinker’s theses are convincing – notably those dealing with torture, hygiene, and literacy – we have good reason to be skeptical of Pinker’s claim that we human beings are less violent than we once were. Much of Pinker’s argument rests upon the scientific and technological conquests of the post-Enlightenment in the West. There may be less hope that human beings have truly mastered the ‘dark sides’ of our natures when we assess just how dependent we are upon the technological management of crises, and further, how our confidence in our superiority in the ‘civilized’ world may depend upon the continuing subordination and domination of large parts of less fortunate humanity.