Displaying: 161-180 of 650 documents

0.071 sec

161. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 17 > Issue: 2
Friedrich Steinle Challenging Established Concepts: Ampère and Exploratory Experimentation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The more unknowns there are and the newer a field of research is, the less well defined are the experiments. Once a field has been sufficiently worked over so that the possible conclusions are more or less limited to existence or nonexistence, and perhaps to quantitative determination, the experiments will become increasingly better defined. But they will no longer be independent, because they are carried along by a system of earlier experiments and decisions, which is generally the situation in physics and chemistry today. Such a system will then become self-evident know-how itself. We will no longer be aware of its application and effect (Fleck 1935 (1980), p. 114, translation slightly altered from Fleck 1979, p. 86, original emphasis).
162. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 17 > Issue: 2
Valeriano Iranzo Constructive Empiricism and Scientific Practice. A Case Study
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to van Fraassen, constructive empiricism (CE) makes better sense of scientific activity than scientific realism (SR). I discuss a recent episode in biomedical research - investigations about Helicobacter Pylori and its relation to peptic ulcer. CE's expedient to cope with it is a sort of belief substitution. I argue that replacing realist beliefs by empiricist surrogates (as-if beliefs) could accommodate scientists' expectations and behavior. Nonetheless, theoretical agnosticism could hardly motivate scientists to focus just on the observational consequences derived from the theory at issue. Contrary to van Fraassen, I conclude then that, concerning scientific practice, realist beliefs cannot be considered as a gratuitious surplus which should be rejected.
163. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 17 > Issue: 2
Diana I. Perez Physicalism, Qualia and Mental Concepts
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I shall carefully examine some recent arguments for dualism. These arguments presuppose a strong version of physicalism that I consider inappropriate. I shall try to show that, if we reformulate the thesis of physicalism according to Kim's view of physicalism (in terms of the supervenience relation), there is a third option, a version of type physicalism, where physicalism and quaiia could be conciliated. In order to sketch this option, I shall consider the main argument against type physicalism: the explanatory gap argument, and two arguments that Kim mentions against physicalism: the inverted spectrum / zombies argument and the intrinsicality argument. I shall try to show that these three arguments depend upon a misconception of the nature of our ordinary mental concepts.
164. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 17 > Issue: 2
Agenda / Notebook
165. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 17 > Issue: 3
Agustín Vicente The Localism of the Conserved Quantity Theory
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Phil Dowe has argued persuasively for a reductivist theory of causality. Drawing on Wesley Salmon's mark transmission theory and David Fair's transferencetheory, Dowe proposes to reduce causality to the exchange of conserved quantities. Dowe's account has the virtue of being simple and offering a definite "visible" idea of causation. According to Dowe and Salmon, it is also virtuous in being localist. That a theory of causation is localist means that it does not need the aid of counterfactuals and/or laws to work. Moreover, it can become the means by which we explain counterfactuals and laws. In this paper, I will argue that the theory is not localist (and hence, that it is less simple than it seems). As far as I can see, the theory needs the aid of laws.
166. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
167. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Gheorghe Paun, Mario J. Pérez-Jiménez Recent Computability Models Inspired from Biology: DNA and Membrane Computing
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
We briefly present two areas of natural computing, vividly investigated in the recent years: DNA computing and membrane computing. Both of them have the roots in cellular biology and are rather developedat the theoretical level (new concepts, models, paradigms of computer science, with mathematical and epistemological significance have been considered in this framework), but both areas are still looking for implementations of a practical interest.
168. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
LIBROS RECIBIDOS / BOOKS RECEIVED
169. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Patrick Blackburn, Johan Bos Computational Semantics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article we discuss what constitutes a good choice of semantic representation, compare different approaches of constructing semantic representations for fragments of natural language, and give an overview of recent methods for employing inference engines for natural language understanding tasks.
170. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
AGENDA / NOTEBOOK
171. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Joerg Flum Descriptive Complexity Theories
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article we review some of the main results of descriptive complexity theory in order to make the reader familiar with the nature of the investigations in this area. We start by presenting the characterization of automata recognizable languages by monadic second-order logic. Afterwards we explain the characterization of various logics by fIxed-point logics. We assume familiarity with logic but try to keep knowledge of complexity theory to aminimum.
172. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Juan José Acero Conceptions of the mind... that do not loose sight of logic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Which is the relation between logic and philosophy of mind? This work tries to answer that question by shortly examining, first, the place that is assigned to logic in three current views of the mind: Computationalism, Interpretativism and Naive Naturalism. Secondly, the classical debate between psychologism and antipsychologism is reviewed -the question about whether logic is or not a part of psychology- and it is indicated in which place of such debate the three mentioned conceptions of mind are located.
173. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Informantes de THEORIA (2000-2002) / Reviewers for 2000-2002
174. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Carlos Martín-Vide, Victor Mitrana Networks of Evolutionary Processors: A Survey
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The goal of this paper is to survey, in a uniform and systematic way, the main results regarding networks of evolutionary processors reported so far. First, we recall the results concerning the computational power of these networks viewed as language generating devices. Then, we briefly present a few NP-complete problems and recall how they were solved in linear time by networks of evolutionary processors with linearly bounded resources (nodes, ruIes, symbols).
175. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Ángel Nepomuceno Presentation: The interdisciplinary field of Logic, Language and Information
176. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
Andoni Ibarra Editor’s Note
177. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
178. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
AGENDA / NOTEBOOK
179. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Manuel García-Carpintero Gómez-Torrente on Modality and Tarskian Logical Consequence
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Gómez-Torrente’s papers have made important contributions to vindicate Tarski’s model-theoretic account of the logical properties in the face of Etchemendy’s criticisms. However, at some points his vindication depends on interpreting the Tarskian account as purportedly modally deflationary, i.e., as not intended to capture the intuitive modal element in the logical properties, that logical consequence is (epistemic or alethic) necessary truth-preservation. Here it is argued that the views expressed in Tarski’s seminal work do not support this modally deflationary interpretation, even if Tarski himself was sceptical about modalities.
180. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Julia Barragán The Perverse Normative Power of Self-Exceptions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One of the most disturbing problems of social decision making and indeed quite difficult to resolve is the need to reconcile individual rationality with that of society. While individual rationalizing rules indicateways to maximize benefits without any restriction, the collective point of view tilts toward the limitation of individual maximization. This is the very core of the so-called Prisoner’s Dilemma which is but a formalway of saying that there is good reason for every individual to defect on a bargain; the ‘good reason’, that generally takes the gentler form of a self-exception, is that if a player defects and his opponent does not, then the former profits. The purpose of this study is to show the highly erosive character of this self-exceptions and also to make evident its perverse normative power.