Narrow search


By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 21-40 of 46 documents

0.084 sec

21. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 5
Special Thanks
22. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 5
Rachel Bayefsky, Erin Miller, Hilary Putnam Interview with Hilary Putnam, Harvard University
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Hilary Putnam is Cogan University Professor Emeritus at Harvard University. He has developed a reputation for excellence in many areas of philosophy, including epistemology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of mind, science and language. A sampling of his books include Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings (1964), Philosophical Papers (1975 and 1983), Reason, Truth, and History (1981), Pragmatism: An Open Question (1995), The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays (2002), Ethics without Ontology (2004), and Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life (2008). This interview was conducted at Harvard on June 15, 2009.
23. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 5
About the Authors
24. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 5
Rachel Bayefsky, Dominic Zarecki Editor's Note
25. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Alice Evans Are We Bound to Uphold Rawlsian Justice?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A Theory of Justice maintains that we are morally bound to further those institutional arrangements that support those principles that would have been agreed to by contracting parties in the original position. However, some critics have rejected the implicit premise that hypothetical contracts yield contractual obligations. But this critique is misplaced according to a different interpretation of the contract’s role. Rawls arguably claims that justice is binding and that in virtue of specifying the content of justice the hypothetical contract is likewise binding. To determine whether we are bound to uphold Rawlsian justice, I shall discuss both approaches and then further analyse charges of triviality, circularity, an alleged similarity to intuitionism and the contractarian rebuttal of utilitarianism.
26. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Bihui^ Li Description in Goethe and Wittgenstein
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Wittgenstein was strongly influenced in his formulation of the role of description in philosophy by Goethe’s conception of description as a scientific method. However, despite retaining some superficial similarities, Wittgenstein’s notion of the role of description in philosophy turns out to be an extreme morph of its scientific predecessor. Wittgenstein extends description’s domain of application to such an extent that, unlike for Goethe, it becomes much more than a method for elucidating facts or principles, and confl icts with some of Goethe’s original reasons for favoring description over explanation.
27. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Daniel Koffler Possibilism and Frege’s Puzzle
28. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
YPR, Ned Block Interview with Ned Block, New York University
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Professor Block has written extensively on a number of topics in the philosophy of mind, from consciousness to cognitive science, and is particularly known for his work on Functionalism. Many of his papers are collected in Consciousness, Functionalism, and Representation (2007). This interview was conducted in New Haven on March 6th, 2007.
29. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Peter Goldstein The Cognitive Command Constraint in Wright’s “Truth and Objectivity”
30. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Linsley­Chittenden Hall, Robert Pippin Interview with Robert Pippin, University of Chicago
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Robert Pippin is the chair of the Committee on Social Thought at the University of Chicago, where he is the Evelyn Stefansson Nef Distinguished Service Professor. Most well-known for his work in German idealism, he is the author of Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness (1989), Modernism as a Philosophical Problem: On the Dissatisfactions of European High Culture (1991), and The Persistence of Subjectivity: On the Kantian Aftermath (2005), among other works. We felt that his insights on a number of topics both philosophical and non-philosophical easily warranted the relatively unedited version you see here. Even so, our discussion with him far outlasted an hour of tape, so a good deal has still been left out. The interview was conducted in Linsley- Chittenden Hall of Yale University on March 28th, 2007.
31. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 3
Jordan Corwin, Yaron Luk-Zilberm Editors' Note
32. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
Brendan Dill Propositions, Clarification, and Faultless Disagreement
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Both contextualist and relativist solutions to the faultless disagreement problem clash with our intuitions: contextualism, with the intuition that two people arguing about a matter oftaste are in fact disagreeing; and relativism, with the intuition that the truth of a proposition is independent of who is evaluating it. In this paper, I will outline a solution that explains our intuition of disagreement without clashing with our intuitions about truth. I will do this by proposing a definition of propositions as ideally clarified assertoric content, having one absolute truth-value that does not vary across any contexts. I will argue that this definition is plausible, that it best serves the purposes of philosophy, and that it best solves the problem of faultless disagreement.
33. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
Jeremy Goodman Dispositional Properties and Humean Supervenience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
David Lewis' thesis of Humean Supervenience combines the claims 1) that there are no necessary connections between distinct existences and 2) that truth supervenes on being. Contra Lewis, we should adopt a dispositional rather than a categorical theory of property individuation. Moreover, contra the conventional wisdom, such a theory is consistent with claim 1). However, it cannot be made consistent with claim 2) without abandoning the standard semantics for counterfactuals.
34. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
Melissa Tan Bringing a Text to Life: The Role of the Reader in Plato's Phaedrus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
ln the Phaedrus, Socrates cnt1c1zes wntmg as non-living and deceptive. He later also claims that a good writer will write only for the sake of self-amusement. These apparent indictments of the written word seem to be at odds with the fact that the Phaedrus is itself a written text, to which Plato has presumably devoted some care and effort. I will show, however, that Plato uses these claims ultimately to suggest that the reader is responsible for transforming a written text into a dialogue with the text's author. I argue that Plato gets this message across via deliberate but not unsubtle flaws in Socrates' arguments and by highlighting the frivolity of written words, thereby directing the careful reader to recognize the significance of what Socrates leaves unsaid. For Plato, what is left unsaid is a more rel iable vehicle for conveying some understanding of reality and truth than mere written words.
35. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
Ian Wells The Third Man Argument, Parmenides 132a1-b2
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Over the last half-century, Plato's Third Man Argument [TMA] has received a surge of attention. The challenge which numerous critics have undertaken is to provide a viable interpretation of Plato's puzzling passage at Parm. 132a1-b2. The exegetical part of this paper attempts to bring together some of the most plausible interpretations offered to date, distilling the good moves from the bad. The not-so-exegetical part of this paper draws out the consequences of these most plausible interpretations. In pa1ticular, it considers the possibility, inspired in the first instance by a stage-functional interpretation of Plato's one-over-many principle, that Plato held a recursive theory of knowledge. In Part I, I give a textual and logical analysis of the TMA I try to formulate the TMA such that it validly generates a regress from consistent premises, while remaining faithful to the text. In Part 11, I ask whether Plato is vulnerable to the TMA so conceived. I argue that some textual evidence suggests that he is not. In Part III, I assume for the sake of argument that Plato is vulnerable, and ask: (1) ls the conclusion of the TMA vicious - does it pose a problem for Plato? And (2), what are the consequences of the IMA (if it goes through) for Plato's claim that knowledge is possible?
36. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
YPR, Daniel Dennett Interview with Daniel Dennett, Tufts University
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Daniel Dennett is the Austin B. Fletcher Professor of Philosophy and Codirector of the Center for Cognitive Studies at Tufts University. His research has centered on philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, with particular interests in cognitive science and evolutionary biology. He is a steadfast and vocal atheist and secularist. His many books have been read widely both in and out of the academy. They include Consciousness Explained (1992), Darwin 's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life ( l 996), and Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (2006). We spoke with Professor Dennett in June 2010.
37. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 6
Chandler Coggins, Hayley Johnson, Geoffrey Shaw Editors' Note
38. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 1
Michael Della Rocca Foreword
39. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 1
D. R. Foster Are There Aristotelian Substances?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
There is a broadly Aristotelian conception of substance, supported in various forms by Aristotle himself, and later by Ayers and Wiggins, which takes substance as the ontologically basic, absolute, persistent, unitary, irreducible, and individual subject of all predicates. This paper interrogates this account in light of the everyday intuitions which underlie it—metaphysical intuitions about the persistence of particulars over time, as well as semantic and linguistic intuitions regarding the practices of individuation and predication. After surveying some of the relevant literature on Aristotelian substance-theory, Foster argues that in its current state, the Aristotelian conception of substance is unattractively dualistic, as well as metaphysically extravagant. As an alternative, the paper argues for a modified “bundle-theory” of substance, which holds that Aristotelian substances can and should be understood as nothing more than structured matter with manifest “bundles” of properties. On this basis, Foster attempts to demonstrate that our semantic and logico-linguistic intuitions can be fruitfully explained and vindicated by a bundle-theory, while remaining agnostic about the richer metaphysics suggested by the Aristotelian theory.
40. The Yale Philosophy Review: Volume > 1
Al Prescott-Couch What is a Mood?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The idea of “moods” is ubiquitous in our everyday lives; theories about mood attempt to capture these commonplace intuitions, while providing a clear and philosophically satisfying definition of the phenomena. In this paper, Prescott-Couch uses a set of criteria suggested by Eric Lormand to evaluate competing theories of mood. Focusing on three of the most plausible accounts—Generalization, Functional Component, and Higher Order Functional State theories—the paper argues that the third view, held by P. E. Griffiths, is the most plausible. Prescott-Couch then entertains objections to the functional approach, paying particular attention to the phemenological worry—that is, that this type of theory fails to grasp at our subjective experience of moods.