Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 1-20 of 23 documents

0.093 sec

1. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 4
Louis Caruana SJ La Science Élimine-T-Elle Le Discours Quotidien?
2. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 4
Roman Darowski SJ L'activité philosophique de Diego Ortiz (1564-1625) en Pologne et en Lituanie
3. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 5
Jerzy Koperek II concetto della persona umana nell'ambito del personalismo di Karol Wojtyła
4. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 5
Antoni Jarnuszkiewicz SJ La méthodologie des analyses de l'expérience de Dieu dans la nouvelle phénoménologie d'Emmanuel Lévinas
5. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 5
Franciszek Bargieł SJ Stanislas Szadurski SJ (1726-1789), un représentant de la Philosophie scolastique modernisée
6. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 6
Tadeusz Ślipko SJ Principes anthropologiques et éthiques des soins palliatifs
7. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 6
Karol Tarnowski Sujet de la guerre, sujet de la paix: (Levinas et Marcel)
8. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 22 > Issue: 2
Carla Canullo Paul Ricoeur: entre attestation du mal et témoignage de l’espérance
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The aim of this article is to show that the “attestation of evil and testimony of hope” are characterized by the genitive that accompanies them. This places them both, each no less than the other, in two different horizons: while the horizon of attestation is Heideggerian, the horizon of testimony is a legacy of Jean Nabert. Both of these horizons are present in the thought of Ricoeur, and characterize the entire spectrum of his work. However, we are not dealing here with a syncretism resulting from the co-presence of a hermeneutic source and of the philosophy of reflection. On the contrary, I attempt to show that the copresence of attestation and testimony results from the fact that Ricoeur never stopped “walking on two legs,” given what he writes in a conversation published in the Critique and Conviction, and that this presence is rooted in Ricoeur’s formation, which is at the same time philosophical, literary and biblical, as he never renounced either the former one, or the latter ones.
9. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 22 > Issue: 2
Catherine Goldenstein L’unité d’une vie, d’un enseignement, d’une oeuvre
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This essay offers a personal account of the author’s friendship and collaboration with Paul Ricoeur in the last years of his life. Catherine Goldenstein, who, after Ricoeur’s death, took care of his manuscripts and organized the archives of the Fonds Ricoeur, reflects on her conversations with the philosopher. Their contents, recorded as she remembers them, illuminate Ricoeur’s philosophical endeavors and his work as an academic instructor. Ricoeur is also viewed through the testimony of letters addressed by him to the author, through his personal notes, and through the events of his academic career. These perspectives combine to offer a concise and challenging vision of a life devoted to reflection, whose ultimate boundary is a reality we do not know directly: that of eternity.
10. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 22 > Issue: 2
Jérôme de Gramont Paul Ricoeur et le destin de la phénoménologie
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Every reader of Ricoeur knows that hermeneutics endeavors to answer the aporiae of historical phenomenology. Hence arises the need to return to those aporiae and those answers. On the one hand, phenomenology, born with the maxim of going “directly to things themselves,” is confronted with the incessant evasion of the thing itself and with its dreams of presence being thereby shattered. This reversal should not be blamed on the failings of this or that thinker, but attributed to the very destiny of phenomenology itself. On the other hand, Ricoeurian hermeneutics takes note of a gap (the very remoteness of the thing itself), and of a necessary return (to the thing of the text). Thus, there is nothing for thought itself to grieve over with respect to this enterprise. However, while the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, faced with the same difficulties, orients itself towards political philosophy, the hermeneutics of Ricoeur rather seeks to lead us to a philosophy of religion. This article hypothesizes that, in spite of the formula (inherited from Thévenaz) of a “philosophy without an absolute,” the thought of Ricoeur heads in fair measure towards the Absolute, and that ontology is not the only name of the Promised Land.
11. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 27 > Issue: 2
Guilhem Causse Le geste : de l’esthétique au kinésique
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The transmission of the craft and the treatment of post-traumatic stress disorder have in common that they involve a relationship of act to act between the master and the apprentice on the one hand, and between the therapist and the patient on the other. Phenomenology has from the outset considered movement as inherent to the flesh: Hardy thus hypothesises that the origin of the flesh is a gesture. For all that, his description remains largely dependent on a flesh that is primarily perceptive: this gesture can thus be qualified as an aesthetic gesture. But if the flesh is as much mobile as it is perceptive, would there not be another gesture that generates the flesh in movement that is not linked to perception? Housset takes a step in this direction and allows us to hypothesize the kinesic gesture which, alone, allows us to account for the two experiences mentioned above.
12. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 27 > Issue: 2
Magdalena Kozak Le rôle de la honte dans la formation de la subjectivité humaine chez Jean-Paul Sartre et Emmanuel Lévinas
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The purpose of the following article is to juxtapose and compare the concept of shame as seen by two contemporary French philosophers, Jean Paul Sartre and Emmanuel Levinas. The fundamental problem that is posed in this article concerns the role and significance of the impact of shame on the formation of human subjectivity. For both J.P. Sartre and E. Levinas, the subject attempts to bear the burden of being in a heroic way and the experience of shame proves to be an important experience in this process. Is it an ontological or ethical experience? Or perhaps metaphysical? For both J.P. Sartre and E. Levinas, shame is a relational experience, i.e., it occurs in relation to You. But does this Other have to come to me from outside? In Sartre’s case, shame appears in the experience of the gaze of the Other, and it is a traumatic experience. The Other interferes with my freedom and challenges me as a subject. The experience of shame makes me aware of my subjugation by the Other. In Levinas, the experience of shame comes originally from within myself. The shame of my own existence demands justification. I can be ashamed in relation to myself. I can be a menace of myself. I don’t need the presence of another human being for this. What unites and what separates the two philosophers in interpreting the experience of shame for human subjectivity?
13. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 28 > Issue: 2
Małgorzata Kowalska Un irréductible rien: Réflexions sur le concept sartrien de la conscience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
By defining consciousness as nothingness or simply as “nothing,” Sartre plays with several meanings of these terms: negativity and negation, distance, indetermination, irreducibility. The nothingness of consciousness takes on an ontological meaning: it is a “tearing away” from being-in-itself, a transcendence understood as the capacity to transcend what is, while retaining an epistemological meaning: it is what cannot be positively determined as “something” or as a property of being. Still, on the epistemological level as well as on the ontological level, it is indeed from “something,” from physical and social being, that the nothingness of consciousness draws its existence and its capacities. In my article, I examine different meanings that can be given to the “nothing” of consciousness in the light of the thought of Sartre himself, emphasizing the difference between two major meanings of negation: as opposition and as indetermination. Then I confront Sartre’s concept of consciousness with more recent considerations of different inspiration, notably from researchers like Chalmers, Damasio, Gallagher, and Zahavi. My thesis is that the Sartrean concept, semi-transcendental and semi-naturalist, does admit the search for a naturalist explanation of consciousness, but assigns its limit precisely through the concept of nothingness.