Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 161-180 of 675 documents

0.097 sec

161. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Neal DeRoo Review of Jacques Derrida: Opening Lines, by Marian Hobson
162. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Malek K. Khazaee Review of Mathematics in Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Reflections on Mathematical Practice, by Lisa A. Shabel
163. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Yves Laberge Review of Ethics: Contemporary Readings, ed. H.J. Gensler, E.W. Spurgin, J.C. Swindal
164. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
L. Sebastian Purcell Review of What White Looks Like: African-American Philosophers on The Whiteness Question, ed. George Yancy
165. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
L. Sebastian Purcell Review of Counter-Experiences: Reading Jean-Luc Marion, ed. Kevin Hart
166. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Steven Ross Review of Moral Literacy, by Barbara Herman
167. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Eric Rovie Review of Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy, by John Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman
168. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Peter Murphy Review of Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Vols. 1 & 2, by Scott Soames
169. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 3
H. Eugene Cline John Rawls’ Law of Peoples: Some of the Important Themes and Issues Raised
170. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 3
Andrew Fiala Terrorism and the Philosophy of History: Liberalism, Realism, and the Supreme Emergency Exemption
171. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
James McBain Issue Introduction
172. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Donald Cross Cartesian “Riddles”: Descartes, Words, and Deduction
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Traditionally, ‘René Descartes’ is synonymous with ‘method.’ The so-called father of modern science, he is perhaps the systematic and methodological philosopher par excellence, a fundamental motivation for his attempt to secede from contemporary thought being the possibility of establishing a universally valid method in the search for truth. In a passage in the Rules for the Direction of the Mind, Descartes contrasts his method with what he calls scholastic “[r]iddles,” verbal equivocations that hinder the acquisition of knowledge. In this paper I analyze this notion of riddling and the Cartesian method to posit that, finally, Descartes cannot avoid replicating the very riddles he criticizes, that his ‘revolutionary’ method only generates more riddles to be methodically solved. In short, Descartes’ method is dependent upon words but also calls for the effacement of the very words that constitute it. Words are both a methodological necessity and limitation; a double bind, there is no method without words, but, at the same time, there can be no method with words, that is, no methodo-logos. In its broadest formulation, Descartes must always at once say too much and too little.
173. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Elizabeth Shaw Is James’s Pragmatism Really a New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Pragmatism may be the aspect of William James’s thought for which he is best known; but, at the same time, James’s pragmatism may be among the most misunderstood doctrines of the past century. There are many meanings of word “pragmatism,” even within James’s own corpus. Not a single unified doctrine, pragmatism may be better described as a collection of positions which together form a coherent philosophical system. This paper examines three interrelated uses of the term: (1) pragmatism as a temperament, (2) pragmatism as a philosophical method, and (3) pragmatism as a “humanistic” and “concrete” theory of knowledge and truth. Some critics infer that pragmatist truth is relative or subjective. This paper concludes with a consideration of James’s responses to such critics. Though James maintains truth is something both “made” and “satisfying,” he just as clearly affirms that as it develops, truth is ever constrained by the elements of extramental reality as well as previously vetted truths. This pragmatist truth is not a function of personal caprice, and the pragmatist is certainly not one who denies an objective order or bends the world to his wishes.
174. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Ben Gibran Philosophy as a Private Language
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Philosophy (and its corollaries in the human sciences such as literary, social and political theory) is distinguished from other disciplines by a more thoroughgoing emphasis on the a priori. Philosophy makes no claims to predictive power; nor does it aim to conform to popular opinion (beyond ordinary intuitions as recorded by ‘thought experiments’). Many philosophers view the discipline’s self-exemption from ‘real world’ empirical testing as a non-issue or even an advantage, in allowing philosophy to focus on universal and necessary truths. This article argues otherwise. The non-instrumentality of philosophical discourse renders it into a collective private language, impairing the discipline’s ability to judge the quality of its own output. The natural sciences and other technical disciplines offer the non-expert ‘windows of scrutiny’ into their respective methodologies, through numerous findings that can be easily and independently tested by amateurs. Such outside scrutiny provides a mechanism of external quality control, mitigating the internal effects of cognitive bias and institutionalised conformity upon the discourses of technical disciplines. In contrast, the conclusions of philosophy are not testable without in-depth knowledge of the methods by which they are arrived at; knowledge which can apparently only be gained through an extensive program of study, in philosophy. This epistemic circularity renders the program (even one of self-study) into a ‘black box’ in which the internal influence of cognitive biases and conformity effects cannot be independently assessed. The black box of philosophy is, in all relevant respects, analogous to the black box of the Cartesian mind that is the subject of Wittgenstein’s private language argument.
175. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Reshef Agam-Segal How to Investigate the Grammar of Aspect-Perception: A Question in Wittgensteinian Method
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I argue that the typical Wittgensteinian method of philosophical investigation cannot help elucidate the grammar of aspect-seeing. In the typical Wittgensteinian method, we examine meaning in use: We practice language, and note the logical ramifications. I argue that the effectiveness of this method is hindered in the case of aspect-seeing by the fact that aspect-seeing involves an aberrant activity of seeing: Whereas it is normally nonsense to say that we choose what to see (decide to see the White House red, for instance), it is possible to see aspects at will—e.g. to decide to see Jastrow’s duck-rabbit as a duck. I suggest an alternative method of investigation, one that reflects on language from a disengaged standpoint: a method that allows us to entertain a form of conceptualization of an object but does not commit us to adopting that way—namely, that does not involve us in a use of the object according to the norms that govern that conceptualization. This method, I argue, fits the subject matter of aspect-perception, since aspect-perception itself involves such a disengaged form of reflection.
176. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Chrysoula Gitsoulis Wittgenstein and Surrealism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
There are two aspects to Wittgenstein’s method of deconstructing pseudo-philosophical problems that need to be distinguished: (1) describing actual linguistic practice, and (2) constructing hypothetical ‘language-games’. Both methods were, for Wittgenstein, indispensable means of clarifying the ‘grammar’ of expressions of our language – i.e., the appropriate contexts for using those expressions – and thereby dissolving pseudo-philosophical problems. Though (2) is often conflated with (1), it is important to recognize that it differs from it in imprtant respects. (1) can be seen as functioning as a direct method of ‘proof’ (i.e., attempt to convince the reader of some thesis), and (2) as an indirect method of ‘proof’ – proof by reduction ad absurdum. This essay will be devoted to clarifying (2) by forging an analogy with surrealism in art.
177. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Brian Talbot Interest as a Starting Place for Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper discusses a puzzle about philosophical beliefs. Core philosophical beliefs that are widely shared among philosophers, such as the belief that skepticism is false, are often held with extreme confidence. However, this confidence is not justified if these beliefs are based on what are traditionally seen as the sources of philosophical evidence, such as intuitions or observation (or reasoning on these bases). Charity requires that we should look for some other basis for these beliefs. I argue that these beliefs are based on our knowledge of what we find interesting. Further, I argue that this is a good basis for belief. Knowing what we find interesting allows us to tune our inquiry in ways we could not otherwise.
178. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Bennett Gilbert Freshest Advices on What To Do With the Historical Method in Philosophy When Using It to Study a Little Bit of Philosophy That Has Been Lost to History
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The paper explores the question of the relationship between the practice of original philosophical inquiry and the study of the history of philosophy. It is written from my point of view as someone starting a research project in the history of philosophy that calls this issue into question, in order to review my starting positions. I argue: first, that any philosopher is sufficiently embedded in culture that her practice is necessarily historical; second, that original work is in fact in part a reconstruction by reinterpretation of the past and that therefore it bears some relation to historiographic techniques for the restoration of damaged objects and texts; and third that the special oddities of the relations of present and past do not fail to ensnare the philosopher, who must restore the past but freely break from it. I describe this relationship as proleptic. Finally, I argue that this is a moral imperative in writing philosophy, derived from the imperative to be honest.
179. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Justin Sytsma, Jonathan Livengood Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Disputes
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One view of philosophy that is sometimes expressed, especially by scientists, is that while philosophers are good at asking questions, they are poor at producing convincing answers. And the perceived divide between philosophical and scientific methods is often pointed to as the major culprit behind this lack of progress. Looking back at the history of philosophy, however, we find that this methodological divide is a relatively recent invention. Further, it is one that has been challenged over the past decade by the modern incarnation of experimental philosophy. How might the reincorporation of empirical methods into philosophy aid the process of making philosophical progress? Building off of the work of Sytsma (2010), we argue that one way it does so is by offering a means of resolving some disputes that arise in philosophy. We illustrate how philosophical disputes may sometimes be resolved empirically by looking at the recent experimental literature on intuitions about reference.
180. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Anthony Bryson, David Alexander The View from the Armchair: Responding to Kornblith’s Alternative to Armchair Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In the last two decades, the greatest threat to armchair philosophy has been the natural kinds approach. On this view, philosophic theorizing should not be obsessed with the ideas of justice, goodness, and truth but should look outward to the world of objects to find these things. And if these things happen to be natural kinds, like kinds of rock or fish for instance, then clearly we should reject the armchair for the lab. The philosopher should leave the office and join the scientist out in the field. Philosophy should become a species of science. We attempt to defend traditional/armchair philosophy by examining Hilary Kornblith’s naturalistic methodological approach to epistemology. Among other things, we argue that Kornblith’s approach leads to some surprising, undesirable results (at least undesirable to the naturalist), one of which is that Kornblith cannot discount epistemic internalism as a viable contender in the search for the nature of knowledge. His methodology actually requires that we take epistemic internalism seriously.