Displaying: 161-180 of 274 documents

0.319 sec

161. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 17 > Issue: 1
John McDowell Autonomy and Its Burdens
162. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Gerald Gaus Moral Constitutions
163. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Fred Dretske Challenging Closure: Is It A Way To Answer The Skeptic?
164. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Samuel Freeman G. A. Cohen's Critique of Rawls's Difference Principle
165. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
P.M.S. Hacker Crane on Intentionality
166. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Thomas C. Brickhouse, Nicholas D. Smith Persuade Or Obey
167. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
A.W. Price Eudaimonism and Egocentricity
168. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
David E. Cooper Beauty and the Cosmos
169. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Judith Jarvis Thomson Killing and Not Preventing Death
170. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Stephen Mulhall Sharing a Dream of Skepticism
171. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 19
Adam Kern, Oliver Wenner Note from the Editors
172. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Samuel Scheffler The Idea of Global Justice: A Progress Report
173. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Jonathan Dancy Berkeley, Descartes and the Science of Nature: (Or How Berkeley Tried to Put the Clock Back)
174. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Richard Healey Quantum Meaning
175. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Pär Sundström Two Types of Qualia Theory
176. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Adrian Moore Some Recent Developments in Philosophy
177. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Richard Schacht Beyond “The Death of God”
178. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Thom Brooks A New Problem with the Capabilities Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Martha Nussbaum’s “influential capabilities approach” offers us a powerful, universal standard of justice. The approach builds off of pioneering work by Amartya Sen in economic development. Much of the contemporary interest in the capabilities approach has focused upon how we might spell out a list of precisely which capabilities must be made universally available and protected, a list that Sen has not provided himself. Nussbaum’s list of capabilities is arguably the most successful attempt at defining these capabilities. In this paper, I will argue for a new problem with the approach that raises new questions about the capabilities approach more generally.
179. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
John Kaag, Jamie Ashton Drone Warfare and the Paradox of Choice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article employs Gerald Dworkin’s analysis in “Is More Choice Better Than Less” (1982) in order to understand the challenges and consequences of having enlarged the scope of military options to include precision guided munitions (PGM) and unmanned aerial vehicle (UAV) capabilities.1 Following Dworkin, we argue that having more strategic choices are not always better than less for a number of specific reasons. Unlike many philosophical discussions of the use of these military technologies, ours is an account of the prudential challenges and consequences of having widened military options, and the analysis self-consciously avoids making moral or legal claims concerning their use. It is simply an examination of the claim that widening the range of tactical options, to include these new weapon systems, is necessarily better. We will follow the outline of Dworkin’s argument in describing the current politico-military affairs. Our intent is to expose the practical costs associated with having tactical choices that include the use of these technologies. To be clear, the argument does not bear directly on the use of these technologies, but rather on the challenges associated with merely having the choice to use these weapon systems. Faced with the challenges associated with the option of having PGM or UAV capabilities, it may be judicious for countries to freely limit the military choices that they have at their disposal. This is not self-evident since the weapon technologies in question are not the sort that poses a clear and present danger to a large number of citizens, as was the case with nuclear weapons limited in the Strategic Arms Limitation Talks (SALT) of the 1970s or 1980s. Therefore a more detailed philosophical argument is warranted. A final caveat needs to be stated: The argument is to be taken as a whole since no single aspect of Dworkin’s analysis is definitive in regard to the question of whether more choice is indeed better than less. Each aspect does, however, contribute to a deeper understanding of what enlarging the set of tactical means for modern militaries.
180. The Harvard Review of Philosophy: Volume > 20
Oliver Cronlinde Wenner Editor's Note