Displaying: 181-200 of 214 documents

0.021 sec

181. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Christopher B. Barrett, Ray Grizzle A Holistic Approach to Sustainability Based on Pluralism Stewardship
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, we advance a holistic ecological approach based on a three-compartment model. This approach favors policy initiatives that lie at the intersection of the three major areas of concern common to most environmental controversies: environmental protection, provision of basic human needs, and advancing economic welfare. In support of this approach, we propose a “pluralistic stewardship”integrating core elements of anthropocentrism, biocentrism, and ecocentrism. After presenting the basics of our model, we then explain why it is important to identify and promote a holistic ecological approach to sustainability. Here we employ the economic concept of path dependence, emphasizing that there exist multiple paths society can follow in environmental ethics and policy but once one has been chosen, implicitly or explicitly, there may be little opportunity to reverse such choices.
182. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Dean W. Boening Biotechnology and Environmental Pollution
183. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Bart Gruzalski Beyond Growth: The Economics of Sustainable Development
184. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Ned Hettinger, Bill Throop Refocusing Ecocentrism: De-emphasizing Stability and Defending Wildness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Traditional ecocentric ethics relies on an ecology that emphasizes the stability and integrity of ecosystems. Numerous ecologists now focus on natural systems that are less clearly characterized by these properties. We use the elimination and restoration of wolves in Yellowstone to illustrate troubles for traditional ecocentric ethics caused by ecological models emphasizing instability in natural systems. We identify several other problems for a stability-integrity based ecocentrism as well. We show how an ecocentric ethic can avoid these difficulties by emphasizing the value of the wildness of natural systems and we defend wildness value from a rising tide of criticisms.
185. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Philip Cafaro Personal Narratives and Environmental Ethics
186. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
Mathew Humphrey Deep Ecology and the Irrelevance of Morality: A Response
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his article “Deep Ecology and the Irrelevance of Morality,” Eric H. Reitan contends that, contrary to the disavowals of Fox and Naess, the “ecosophy T” concept of “Self-realization” constitutes a precondition of morality according to a “robust” Kantian moral framework. I suggest that there is a significant problem involved in rendering Self-realization compatible with a Kantian moral framework. This problem of ontological priority demonstrates that Naess and Fox are in fact correct in their assertion that Self-realization is a nonmoral phenomenon.
187. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1
NEWS AND NOTES
188. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Megs S. Gendreau Anna Wienhues. Ecological Justice and the Extinction Crisis: Giving Living Beings Their Due
189. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Kenneth Shockley Simon James. How Nature Matters: Culture, Identity, and Environmental Value
190. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Colin H. Simonds The Trouble of Rocks and Waters: On the (Im)Possibility of a Buddhist Environmental Ethic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article considers the possibility of constructing an authentic environmental ethic from Buddhist sources. It first outlines the major critiques of historical Buddhist approaches to the natural world and parses some of the philological and linguistic barriers to such a construction. It then considers some of the recent philosophical critiques of such a project and reviews the major points of tension between the Buddhist philosophical tradition and the kinds of environmental ethics found in the land ethic and deep ecology. Ultimately, this article asserts that such tension is relieved if we begin from Buddhist philosophical principles and construct an environmental ethic from the ground up. It argues a Buddhist environmental ethic emerges from the combination of the goal of liberating all sentient beings from duḥkha, an understanding of duḥkha as dependently arising, and a novel recognition of the environment as a major cause of this duḥkha.
191. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Yasha Rohwer Evolution Is Not Good
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Many environmental ethicists think evolutionary processes are good or, put differently, that they are morally valuable. Furthermore, many claim this value can be compromised when humans disrupt or cause a break in these processes. In this paper, I argue this account is mistaken. Evolution is not good. Furthermore, evolution cannot be “broken” by mere human involvement. There is no preordained trajectory in evolution; randomness, genetic drift, and historical contingency influence all evolutionary histories. Additionally, to think humans necessarily undermine so-called “natural” processes and turn them artificial is to ignore Vogel (2011, 2015), and insist on pre-Darwinian dualism. There is no morally meaningful distinction between natural selection and artificial selection; they are both simply selection. Furthermore, animals shape their own evolutionary trajectories, their progenies’, and those of other organisms through their intentions and choices—as is illustrated in the theory of niche construction. Human involvement in evolutionary processes does not “break” them nor does it necessarily reduce the value of the end products of those processes.
192. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Philip Cafaro Procreation and Consumption in the Real World
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The cause of global environmental decline is clear: an immense and rapidly growing human economy. In response, environmentalists should advocate policies leading to fewer people, lower per capita consumption, and less harmful technologies. All three of these must be addressed, not just one instead of the others. That is our best remaining hope to create sustainable societies and preserve what global biodiversity remains. Sharing Earth justly with other species and protecting it for future human generations are achievable goals, but only if we recognize limits to growth, show restraint in both consumption and procreation, replace maximizing thinking with sufficiency thinking, and cultivate gratitude for what we receive from nature. Efficiency cannot take the place of ethics. Cleverness cannot take the place of wisdom. Humanity must learn to recognize and appreciate ‘enough.’
193. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Kalle Grill Procreation vs. Consumption: Harms and Benefits
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Recently, it has been argued by several scholars that we have moral reasons to limit our procreation due to the harmful environmental consequences it entails. These calls for procreative restraint are typically made in relation to other lifestyle choices, such as minimizing driving and air travel. In such comparisons, it is assumed that the environmental impact of procreation encompasses the lifetime consumption of the child created, and potentially that of further descendants. After an overview of these arguments, I go on to provide an examination of the main benefits of procreation, in relation to those of consumption, i.e., other lifestyle choices. My normative assumption is that benefits hold moral relevance, alongside harms. Procreation may benefit procreators and may provide more collective benefits. Some benefits tend to preempt the environmental impact associated with procreation. I conclude that the benefits of procreation are substantial and typically greater than those of consumption.
194. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Travis N. Rieder Contributory Reasons For and Against Procreation: Reply to Grill
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Procreative limitarians, according to Kalle Grill, believe that we—especially the globally wealthy—should limit our procreative behaviors in order to reduce our impact on the natural environment. However, according to Grill, limitarians tend not to perform a complete moral analysis of procreating, as they cite the costs without noting the substantial benefits. In particular, Grill argues that procreation has benefits that consumption lacks, which is relevant for deciding where to focus in our efforts to mitigate environmental harms. As one of the limitarians cited by Grill, I think this is an interesting argument to consider, but I will here suggest that it does not succeed in fully responding to the force of the limitarian position.
195. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Corey Katz What We Owe to Animals: Recognizing Animals’ Negative Rights by Making Contractualism Inclusive
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The author argues non-human, sentient animals have aggregation-trumping rights by explaining why and how they should be included in the scope of Kantian contractualism. He explains that the beings to whom we owe duties—who can be wronged by our treatment—are all those with the capacity for first-person, subjective experience; i.e., all sentient beings. To determine what duties we owe to such beings, we should reflect on the principles for the general regulation of behavior that could be hypothetically justified to their imaginary perfectly reasonable counterparts; i.e., even though animals actually cannot understand or reflect on the reasons we have for treating them in a particular way, burdening them unjustifiably is wrong to them. The author argues this inclusive contractualist theory can explain all the distinctive moral phenomena that T. M. Scanlon’s approach does and so is a more attractive contractualist moral theory.
196. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Marion Hourdequin, Katie McShane Guest Editors' Introduction to the 2022 ISEE Special Issue
197. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Index to Volume 45
198. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Referees 2023
199. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Alina Anjum Ahmed Colonialism, Environmental Policy, and Epistemic Injustice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper explores environmental protection policies and initiatives, such as conservation, through the lens of an orientalist epistemic injustice. This is a form of epistemic injustice that occurs when the orientalizing of space and access to sovereign systems of knowledge causes the assigning of an unjust deflated or elevated level of credibility to a knower. Under this framework of orientalist epistemic injustice, the author criticizes the credibility excess assigned to Western subjects that perform conservation efforts in third-world countries and the related credibility deficit assigned to indigenous and local knowledge and conservation practices.
200. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Arthur R. Obst Flying from History, Too Close to the Sun: The Anxious, Jubilant Futurism of Contemporary “Age of Man” Environmentalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
There is a remarkable trend in contemporary environmentalism that emphasizes ‘accepting responsibility’ for the natural world in contrast to outdated preservationist thinking that shirks such responsibility. This approach is often explained and justified by reference to the anthropocene: this fundamentally new epoch—defined by human domination—requires active human intervention to avert planetary catastrophe. However, in this paper, I suggest this rhetoric encourages a flight from history. This often jubilant, sometimes anxious, yearning for unprecedented human innovation and—ultimately—control in our new millennia mirrors the Futurist movement that took off near the beginning of the last century. Despite the significant differences in the details of how academics have defended this twenty-first-century environmental outlook, they all represent the true flight from history; they too quickly jettison the ideas of historical environmentalists and so misunderstand the environmental values at the heart of preservation that are more salient than ever.