Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 201-220 of 317 documents

0.149 sec

201. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Hendrik R. Pieterse Neopragmatism and the Christian Desire for a Transcendent God: Is a Meaningful Dialogue Possible?
202. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Charbel Niño El-Hani, Sami Pihlström Emergence Theories and Pragmatic Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The tradition of pragmatism has, especially since Dewey, been characterized by a commitment to nonreductive naturalism. The notion of emergence, popular in the early decades of the twentieth century and currently re-emerging as a central concept in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, may be useful in explicating that commitment. The present paper discusses the issue of the reality of emergent properties, drawing particular attention to a pragmatic way of approaching this issue. The reality of emergents can be defended as a pragmatically-useful ontological commitment; hence, pragmatism can be employed as a tool in the debate over the structure and reality of emergence. This strategy of justifying ontological commitments is examined through historical and systematic discussions of the pragmatist tradition. It turns out, among other things, that while classical pragmatists did not specify any technical notion of emergence in the contemporary sense, their non-reductively naturalist views are relevant to the more recent emergence discussions -- especially because they rejected the metaphysical realism typical of today’s ontologically-oriented emergence theories.
203. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Gregory M. Fahey The Idea of the Good in John Dewey and Aristotle
204. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Kevin Decker Habermas on Human Rights and Cloning: A Pragmatist Response
205. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Mark McEvoy Naturalized Epistemology, Normativity and the Argument Against the A Priori
206. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
Brian E. Butler Legal Pragmatism: Banal or Beneficial as a Jurisprudential Position?
207. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
D. S. Clark Pragmatism’s Instrumental View of Moral Reasoning
208. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
Dennis R. Cooley Medical Research Ethics: Introduction
209. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
David Rudge Do Unknown Risks Preclude Informed Consent?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Allen Buchanan and Daniel Brock, in a widely influential account, Deciding for Others (1990), advocate a sliding scale approach to the determination of whether a patient is competent to make a decision regarding his/her health care. An analysis of two critiques of their position (Beauchamp and Childress (1994), Wicclair (1991 a,b)) reveals a tacit presumption by all of these authors that the greater cognitive challenge often posed by high risk therapies constitutes grounds for an elevated standard of competence. This presumption cannot be consistently maintained in cases where the patient's decision involves experimental therapies. It implies either that informed consent can never take place in such situations, or, perhaps even more counter-intuitively, that a lower standard of competency should be used than when the patient is asked to choose only among standard therapies.
210. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
Richard B. Miller How the Belmont Report Fails
211. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
William Fish The Direct/Indirect Distinction in Contemporary Philosophy of Perception
212. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Paul Coates Wilfrid Sellars, Perceptual Consciousness and Theories of Attention
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The problem of the richness of visual experience is that of finding principled grounds for claims about how much of the world a person actually sees at any given moment. It is argued that there are suggestive parallels between the two-component analysis of experience defended by Wilfrid Sellars, and certain recently advanced information processing accounts of visual perception. Sellars' later account of experience is examined in detail, and it is argued that there are good reasons in support of the claim that the sensory nonconceptual content of experience can vary independently of conceptual awareness. It is argued that the Sellarsian analysis is not undermined by recent work on change blindness and related phenomena; a model of visual experience developed by Ronald Rensink is shown to be in essential harmony with the framework provided by Sellars, and provides a satisfactory answer to the problem of the richness of visual experience.
213. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
David DeMoss Hunting Fat Gnu: How to Identify a Proxytype
214. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Jeffrey S. Galko Ontology and Perception
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The ontological question of what there is, from the perspective of common sense, is intricately bound to what can be perceived. The above observation, when combined with the fact that nouns within language can be divided between nouns that admit counting, such as ‘pen’ or ‘human’, and those that do not, such as ‘water’ or ‘gold’, provides the starting point for the following investigation into the foundations of our linguistic and conceptual phenomena. The purpose of this paper is to claim that such phenomena are facilitated by, on the one hand, an intricate cognitive capacity, and on the other by the complex environment within which we live. We are, in a sense, cognitively equipped to perceive discrete instances of matter such as bodies of water. This equipment is related to, but also differs from, that devoted to the perception of objects such as this computer. Behind this difference in cognitive equipment underlies a rich ontology, the beginnings of which lies in the distinction between matter and objects. The following paper is an attempt to make explicit the relationship between matter and objects and also provide a window to our cognition of such entities.
215. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Massimo Grassia Consciousness and Perceptual Attention: A Methodological Argument
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Our perception of external features comprises, among others, functional and phenomenological levels. At the functional level, the perceiver’s mind processes external features according to its own causal-functional organization. At the phenomenological level, the perceiver has consciousness of external features. The question of this paper is: How do the functional and the phenomenological levels of perception relate to each other? The answer I propose is that functional states of specifically perceptual attention constitute the necessary basis for the arising of consciousness in a perceiver.Widely studied within cognitive psychology, perceptual attention is still awaiting a thoroughgoing philosophical treatment. The paper presents and draws upon Anne Treisman’s feature-integration theory of attention (cf. A. Treisman & G. Gelade, “A Feature-Integration Theory of Attention,” Cognitive Psychology, 12, 1980. Pp. 97-136). According to this theory, attentional mechanisms are responsible for the binding of perceptual features into coherent and stable objects of perception. By itself, I will claim, the theory of feature integration does not allow a straightforward reduction of consciousness to the functional processing underlying it. However, on the basis of Treisman’s theory we can produce a methodological argument for endorsing the non-reductivist thesis that attentional states constitute the necessary basis for the arising of consciousness in a perceiver. The paper closes by presenting this argument, according to which the thesis is implied by a unified account of the common representational natures of attentional and conscious states.
216. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
David Newman Chaos and Qualia
217. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 1
Uriah Kriegel Perceptual Experience, Conscious Content, and Non-Conceptual Content
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One of the promising approaches to the problem of perceptual consciousness has been the representational theory, or representationalism. The idea is to reduce the phenomenal character of conscious perceptual experiences to the representational content of those experiences. Most representationalists appeal specifically to non-conceptual content in reducing phenomenal character to representational content. In this paper, I discuss a series of issues involved in this representationalist appeal to non-conceptual content. The overall argument is the following. On the face of it, conscious perceptual experience appears to be experience of a structured world, hence to be at least partly conceptual. To validate the appeal to non-conceptual content, the representationalist must therefore hold that the content of experience is partly conceptual and partly non-conceptual. But how can the conceptual and the non-conceptual combine to form a single content? The only way to make sense of this notion, I argue, leads to a surprising consequence, namely, that the representational approach to perceptual consciousness is a disguised form of functionalism.
218. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Steven Benko Ethics, Technology, and Posthuman Communities
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
As long as technology has been interpreted as an expression of practical reasoning and an effort to alter the conditions of human existence, ethical language has been used to interpret and critique technology’s meaning. When this happens technology is more than implements that are expressions of human intelligence and used towards practical ends in the natural world.1 As Frederick Ferre points out, technology is always about knowledge and values—what people want and what they want to avoid—and to the extent that technology increases power, one has to ask whether technology and/or the use towards which it is put is ethical.2 The ethicality of technology is based on whether that technology threatens or enhances the good for human beings. Therefore, any understanding of technology is never removed from ethics. Beyond the ethical evaluation of technology, technology is critiqued in light of whether it enhances or diminishes what it means to be human.
219. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Peter H. Denton Introduction: On the Nature of Technology
220. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Christine James Sonar Technology and Shifts in Environmental Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
For a philosopher, the history of sonar technology is fascinating. During the first and second World Wars, sonar technology was primarily associated with activity on the part of the sonar technicians and researchers. Usually this activity is concerned with creation of sound waves under water, as in the classic “ping and echo”. The last fifteen years have seen a shift toward passive, ambient noise “acoustic daylight imaging” sonar. Along with this shift a new relationship has begun between sonar technicians and environmental ethics.