Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 201-220 of 282 documents

0.079 sec

201. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Greg Moses, Sanjay Lal From Canons of Peace to Shoots of Resistance: Editors' Introduction
202. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Douglas Allen Mahatma Gandhi’s Philosophy of Nonviolence and Truth: The Key Values and Concepts for Gandhi 150 and the Future
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In commemoration of the 150th birthday of M. K. ‘Mahatma’ Gandhi, Douglas Allen, author of Gandhi After 9/11, presents an overview of Gandhi’s philosophy focused on two key values or concepts: Truth (Satya) and Nonviolence (Ahimsa). The presentation is offered as an alternative to non-Gandhians, anti-Gandhians, or reactionary Gandhians who often over-idealized the man and his philosophy. With respect to Ahimsa or Nonviolence, it may be easy to see how the value works against overt, physical violence. However, for Gandhi such examples are only a small part of violence overall. For Gandhi, violence and nonviolence are multidimensional, encompassing our personal ego-driven desires and our widespread economic exploitations. Each dimension of violence or nonviolence is both causal and conditioning, beginning with the experiences of children. Ahimsa should therefore be approached as relational and interconnected. Gandhi approaches the structural violence of the status quo by insisting upon transformative structural nonviolence. Gandhi’s approach to Truth or Satya requires a distinction between Absolute Truth and relative truth. Although Gandhi works with an experiential knowledge of Absolute Truth, he was not an absolutist. Gandhi’s primary focus was upon relative truth, which yields temporary and imperfect ‘glimpses’ of the absolute. In relations with others, we seek kinship with bearers of relative truth. This is the significance of Gandhi’s claim that means and ends are intertwined. With others we seek mutual discovery of relative truths generating greater relative truth. Gandhi’s well known Absolute Nonviolence may prevent us from apprehending its relationship to relative transformations in contextual situations.
203. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Contributors
204. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Court D. Lewis, Gregory L. Bock, David Boersema, Jennifer Kling Author Court D. Lewis Meets Critics on Repentance and the Right to Forgiveness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Court D. Lewis, author of Repentance and the Right to Forgiveness, presents a rights-based theory of ethics grounded in eirenéism, a needs-based theory of rights (inspired by Nicholas Wolterstorff) that seeks peaceful flourishing for all moral agents. This approach creates a moral relationship between victims and wrongdoers such that wrongdoers owe victims compensatory obligations. However, one further result is that wrongdoers may be owed forgiveness by victims. This leads to the “repugnant implication” that victims may be wrongdoers who do not forgive. Author Lewis addresses the “repugnant implication” by showing that victims are obligated to work toward forgiveness, if not forgiveness itself. Critic Gregory L. Bock argues that victims are not the only ones who can forgive, that the personal dimensions of forgiveness are overlooked, and that the force of the “repugnancy implication” may be questioned. Instead of rights-based eirenéism, Bock supports a virtue ethics framework. Instead of rights-based eirenéism, Bock encourages virtue ethics. Critic David Boersema raises questions about the binding nature of relationships, the dependency of flourishing upon forgiveness, and the nature of needs or rights. Boersema also questions the wisdom of a rights-based approach to forgiveness. Critic Jennifer Kling asks whether a rights-based approach is necessary to ground obligations to meet the needs of others: why not an ethics of care? If a rights-based approach is taken, perhaps a wrongdoer is obligated to not make forgiveness a life good. By disengaging this obligation, we avoid constraining a victim’s work toward forgiveness, especially when the wrongdoing is oppressive. Author Lewis responds to these objections.
205. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Matthew Rukgaber Peace and the Unity of Kant’s Critical Project: Review of Philip J. Rossi, The Ethical Commonwealth in History: Peace-making as the Moral Vocation of Humanity
206. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Charles K. Fink Acting Out the Kingdom of God: Review of Predrag Cicovacki and Heidi Nada Grek, editors, Tolstoy and Spirituality
207. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Marilyn Fischer Hull House, the Pullman Strike, and Tolstoy: Documenting the Work of Jane Addams: Review of Mary Lynn McCree Bryan, Maree de Angury, and Ellen Skerrett, editors, The Selected Papers of Jane Addams, Volume III: Creating Hull-House and an International Presence, 1889–1900
208. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Court Lewis The Gift of Kwe: A Present of Radical Resurgence: Review of Leanne Betasamosake Simpson, As We Have Always Done: Indigenous Freedom Through Radical Resistance
209. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Walter Kendall A New Story for a Politics of Belonging: Review of George Monbiot, Out of the Wreckage: A New Politics for an Age of Crisis
210. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Paula Smithka Resisting the Many Faces of Violence: Review of Jennifer Kling, editor, Pacifism, Politics, and Feminism: Intersections and Innovations
211. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Anthony Sean Neal Thurman and King as Transformative Philosophers of Life, Existence, and Community Development During Times of Unchecked Oppression
212. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Anthony Sean Neal, Michael Barber, Eddie O’Byrn Thurman’s Philosophical De-Mystified Mysticism: Author Meets Critics: Anthony Sean Neal, Author of Howard Thurman’s Philosophical Mysticism Meets Critics Michael Barber and Eddie O’Byrn
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this author-meets critics discussion of Howard Thurman’s Philosophical Mysticism, Anthony Sean Neal argues that Thurman’s work requires systematic recognition of how he was rooted firmly within the Modern Era of the African American Freedom Struggle (1896–1975). Michael Barber suggests that Thurman may be understood in contrast to Levinas on two counts. Whereas Thurman develops the duty to love from within the one who must love, Levinas grasps the origin of love’s duty in the command of the one who is to be loved. And while Thurman’s mysticism yearns for oneness, Levinas warns that oneness is ethically problematic. Eddie O'Byrn challenges the symbolic validity of calling love a weapon, and asks why the book has not treated Thurman’s relations to Gandhi or King. Neal defends a provisional usage of the term weapon in relation to love and offers some preliminary considerations of Thurman’s relation to Gandhi and King, especially in the symbolic significance of "the dream."
213. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Anthony Sean Neal “A Fulfillment So High”: New Directions in African American Philosophy for the Study of Howard Thurman and Martin Luther King, Jr.
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Scholarship on Martin Luther King, Jr., and more recent works on Howard Thurman, have become widely appreciative of their contributions to a struggle for Black liberation. This study explicates how the philosophies of Thurman and King also contribute to a universal theme of self-transformation. To be sure, the challenge of self-transformation is aggravated by the oppressive circumstances faced by Black persons in a racist society; however, the resources offered by Thurman and King for personal transformation should be relevant to persons almost regardless of circumstance. This study presents four concepts shared in the personal-transformation philosophies of Thurman and King: (1) Existential Transformation, (2) Self-Altered Destiny, (3) Self Examination, and (4) Rejection of Irrelevance. These four concepts provide a new framework for reading Thurman’s and King’s writings in tandem with a view towards self-transformation and demonstrate why a philosophy of the Black experience would be of interest, and have benefit, for anyone.
214. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
J. Edward Hackett Kingian Personalism, Moral Emotions, and Emersonian Perfectionism: A Response to Paul C. Taylor
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In “Moral Perfectionism,” an essay in To Shape a New World, Paul C. Taylor explicitly mentions and openly avoids King’s personalism while advancing a type of Emersonian moral perfectionism motivated by a less than adequate reconstruction of King’s project. In this essay, I argue this is a mistake on two fronts. First, Taylor’s moral perfectionism gives pride of place to shame and self-loathing where the work of King makes central use of love. Second, by evading the personalist King, Taylor misses the importance of love as foundational to King’s theory of community, the Beloved Community. In effect, Taylor engages in hermeneutic violence regarding King’s work and self-description as a personalist. I offer an account of King’s love informed by personalism that better situates love and shows why it is central to King’s philosophy. In conclusion I argue the following: Love is a type of orientation, attitude, and standpoint one can take in relation to another person. Philia and eros forms of love are contingent and conditional. Agapic love opens up persons to see the eternal dignity we all possess and is restorative and generative of community. The Holy Spirit that animates King’s conception of history is made manifest or hindered by the choice to act on the agapic principle of love that animates the cosmos. In the end, I suggest that Taylor’s perfectionist insights might be applied to a supplemental development of Kingian moral philosophy in the direction of a fuller virtue ethics.
215. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Larry Perry Beyond Black Churches: Toward an Understanding of the Black Spiritual Left, featuring Du Bois, Bethune, Thurman, and Black Lives Matter
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Drawing upon Leigh Schmidt’s work on the “spiritual left,” this article presents a genealogy of the Black Spiritual Left featuring W. E. B. Du Bois, Mary McLeod Bethune, Howard Thurman, and Black Lives Matter activists Opal Tometi and Patrisse Cullors. Black Spiritual Leftists are defined as Black figures who separated from or were not part of Black churches and yet took on a spiritual orientation important to their progressive activism. Their faith is Spiritual, but not necessarily religious. In its most recent manifestation, the Black Spiritual Left argues—in opposition to some Black Church pastors—that defense of Black lives requires respect for marginalized Black women, LGBTQ, and criminalized Black men and boys.
216. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Contributors
217. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Paul C. Taylor Reading King’s Personalism, Or Not: A Reply to Professor Hackett
218. The Acorn: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1/2
Acknowledgments
219. The Acorn: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1/2
Greg Moses Holding Firm to Nonviolence in Spirit, Theory, and Practice
220. The Acorn: Volume > 21 > Issue: 1/2
Rajmohan Gandhi Nationhood Today in the US and India: Learning with Gandhi
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The drives of white nationalism in the US and Hindu nationalism in India are found to be significantly similar in aim and methods. Witnessed in two large nations that are alike too in diversity and in constitutions, the two drives violate statutory norms as also the norms of democracy and equality acknowledged by the world. Contrasting these drives with Gandhi’s vision of partnership and mutual respect among communities and races is illuminating. It may be seen, in addition, that both white nationalism and Hindu nationalism rest on a falsification of history. Stirring up and employing a sentiment of majority victimhood, and another sentiment of dislike for the minority “other,” the two drives present a challenge to all who regard humanity as one and human beings as equal.