Displaying: 61-80 of 636 documents

0.187 sec

61. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 23
Ernst Cassirer, Pedro M. S. Alves, Antonieta Lopes Ernst Cassirer - A “Tragédia da Cultura”
62. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 23
Jesús Blanco Echauri Espinosa Revisitado en Lengua Portuguesa: Filosofia y Política en el Fin de Siècle
63. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 23
António Palhinha Machado, António Pedro Mesquita Um Pioneiro do Liberalismo Económico em Portugal. Notas de Leitura sobre a Guerra e o Comércio Livre de Frederico de la Figanière
64. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 23
Renato Epifânio Repertório da Bibliografia Filosófica Portuguesa (1988-2002)
65. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Maria Luísa Ribeiro Ferreira Abertura
66. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Aylton Barbieri Durão A Fundamentação Kantiana do Estado de Direito
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Kant intends to present a Foundation of the state of right based on the reconstruction of Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s thought. Like the Genevanese philosopher who presents an empirical explanation based on the evolutionary anthropology, and a rational Foundation, based on the political and juridical philosophy, Kant also imagines two ways to fundament the state of right. In his empirical explanation, along with the anthropology, he introduces the history philosophy, which considers that the unsociable sociability makes the humankind leave its state of nature and establish, by means of an usurper, the civil state, in which it gradually approaches the republican constitution and, later, the States Federation and the cosmopolitan right; the rational Foundation, on the other hand, shows how the original contract indirectly determines the Foundation of the civil state, to the extent that only through it is it possible to establish the presumption of the right to the private property that will just turn effective in the civil state itself, although the public right directly postulates the state fundament, which is obtained analytically from the principle of the right in opposition to the concept of violence.
67. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Adelino Braz Kant et la Communauté: Une Philosophie aux Antipodes du Monologisme
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Contra uma interpretação que reduz a filosofia normativa de Kant a um simples monologismo, a nossa leitura pretende mostrar que o projeto de Kant tem por finalidade a instituição de uma comunidade, ou seja de uma coexistência de liberdades interiores. De facto, desde a obra de 1781, as determinações dos fenómenos são unicamente possíveis através do conceito de acção recíproca. A partir deste ponto, Kant retoma o conceito de comunidade (Gemeinschaft) para constituir um mundo moral, ou seja uma interpersonalidade tanto no âmbito estético, através da comunicabilidade dos sentimentos, de um sentido comum (Gemeinsinn), como no âmbito da ética, onde cada ser é ao mesmo tempo membro e legisador dessa comunidade (gemeines Wesen).
68. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Vítor Moura Velocidade e Acordo: O Carácter Metafórico das Ideias Estéticas
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In section 49 of his Critique of Judgement, Kant uses the expression “in Schwung verstezt” in order to classify the free play of the faculties when they get involved with aesthetic ideas. “Schwung” shares the same etymological root of “swing” and suggests, literally, a shuttle-like movement for the non-stop exchange of data between the faculties. This text aims at demonstrating that an interpretation closer to the German original text throws a new light upon the nature of the cognitive play driven by aesthetic ideas. Such interpretation may help to understand, for instance, the reason why Kant uses metaphors as examples of aesthetic ideas. Etymologically, “metaphor” also means “transportation” or “to carry over”. Rather than the notion of a juxtaposition of distant semantic domains, this text wishes to employ the sheer dynamics inherent to the concept of metaphor. This dynamic character is useful in order to reinforce the plausibility of a more cinematic reading, so to speak, of Kant’s conception of aesthetic experience.
69. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Viriato Soromenho-Marques Sombras e Luzes no Entusiasmo em Kant
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper tackles the complex nature of the concept of enthusiasm in three distinct moments of Kant’s thought. It pervades along the different evolutionary periods of the critical philosophy, both as a symptom of the most ugly features of human condition and as a sign of the way human beings are invited and commanded to take part in the process of fulfîlling the tasks and promises of a moral rational world order.
70. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Luisa Leal de Faria A Faculdade de Filosofia de Kant e a Ideia Alemã de Universidade
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Kant’s small essay The Conflict of the Faculties was considered by Derrida a blueprint of the modern university, to be born a few years after its publication, through the works of Humboldt, Fichte, Schelling and Schleiermacher. According to Derrida, the concept of a Philosophical Faculty at the centre of the university, responsible for reason and truth, is now extinct. This paper tries to follow the arguments produced by the founding fathers of the modern university, and the way they were recovered at different points in time, by Nietzsche, Heidegger, Jaspers and Habermas, to show that through two centuries of change, the German Idea of the university kept in touch with the main arguments developed by Kant.
71. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Maria Luísa Ribeiro Ferreira A Crítica de Hume a Espinosa a Propósito da Noção de Substância
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Ce texte veut démontrer que la critique faite par Hume à Spinoza, dans le Traité de la Nature Humaine (I, IV, V) ne respecte pas le concept de Substance utilisé par le philosophe juif. Hume n’a pas lu l'Éthique et il utilise Pierre Bayle comme médiateur pour exposer les thèses de Spinoza, qu’il approche des thèses des théologiens sur l'immortalité de l’âme. Son argumentation est rhétorique et son utilisation de Spinoza est une stratégie pour empêcher qu’on l'accuse d’athéisme.
72. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Leonel Ribeiro dos Santos Regresso a Kant. Sobre a Evolução e a Situação Actual dos Estudos Kantianos
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Le propos de cet essai c’est de donner une idée de la présence de la philosophie kantienne dans les débats philosophiques contemporains. Pour comprendre ce que certains auteurs interprètent déjà comme un nouveau «retour à Kant» ou même comme la survivance d’un «moment kantien de la philosophie», on a esquissé d’abord l’histoire de l’herméneutique de la philosophie kantienne dans la première partie du XXe siècle dans ses moments plus significatifs (le neokantisme, l’interprétation heideggerienne) pour faire ensuite un bilan des tendances de lecture de l’oeuvre de Kant et d’apropriation de sa philosophie après la Deuxième Guerre Mondiale et surtout dans les trois derniers decénnies du XXe siècle. Ce bilan montre l’ampleur de l’actualité de la pensée du professeur de Königsberg et son pouvoir de donner encore à penser les plus décisives questions de la philosophie en tous ses domaines fondamentaux.
73. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 12 > Issue: 24
Renato Epifânio Bibliografia Kantiana em Portugal e no Brasil: 1914-2004
74. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
Maria Luísa Ribeiro Ferreira Abertura
75. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
José de Almeida Pereira Arêdes Ética e Consciência
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This reflection on ethics has starting point problem: the authenticity. What does one understand by authenticity in human life? Will not authenticity be a beautiful dream, a wandering of philosophers? Our everyday experience fully shows the use of the mask. So, we can ask ourselves: 1) Why should it be otherwise? 2) Could it be otherwise? 3) Which means should one use so that it is otherwise? There seem to exist in nature and history three forces in continuous fight: 1st) the ones that cause the misfortune that now we experience. 2nd) the ones that impel us to refuse the misfortune, that is, the ones that motivate us in search of happiness. The 3rd is, perhaps, our voluntary and conscious contribution to awakening. So our problem is not - what must I do?, but - how must I be? The difference has to do with the basic difference between morality and ethics and has roots in our history. My proposal suggests that it is not enough that we dream or desire to act well to actually act well. It is necessary that we have knowledge (of ourselves and the others) and that we have power, mainly on ourselves. However, our experience shows how fragile is the knowledge that we possess of ourselves (and so refusing the well-known socratic invitation “know thyself") and how fragile is that power, because we are constantly carried along by what we do not want to do (and so we ignore Lao Dzi’s lesson “the one that wins the others is strong; but the one that wins himself is really powerful"). But there is more: though we do what we want, who is it in ourselves that wants what we want? Thus, a practical inquiry on ourselves seems primordial in order to verify which forces act in us and, eventually, to start trying to understand them and to guide them in a more beneficial direction for all the community of living beings of the planet that we inhabit together. Being so, ethics is not only a set of theoretical principles, but over all a set of exercises, guided by a knowledge, that could be able to lead us to a different way of being.
76. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
João Paulo Monteiro Realismo Semântico e Consciência do Momento
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
An article by Moulines presents an interesting argument against semantic realism, using Calderôn’s play La Vida en Sueño as a literary device to develop his point. He introduces in the play a new character, a realist philosopher who tries to persuade Prince Segismund to abandon the anti-realist position he maintains, after the experience he undergoes in the play. I introduce a second imaginary realist, who argues for conjectural realism instead of the semantic variety, by means of several sceptical arguments intended to defeat scepticism itself, throwing it in the same boat as anti-realist solipsism.
77. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
Sônia T. Felipe Natureza e Moralidade. Igualdade Antropomórfica, Antropocêntrica, ou Ética?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
La tradition hébraïque, la philosophie d’Aristote, l’impérialisme romain et le christianisme qui les synthétise, ont comme thèse, non seulement la distinction mais la supériorité de la nature humaine face aux autres espèces vivantes. La raison ou la capacité de raisonnement, la conscience et le langage sont des attributs exclusifs de l’espèce humaine, affirment les philosophes moralistes traditionnels. Tous ceux qui les possèdent sont égaux. Les autres êtres, destitués de ces attributs spécifiques, sont différents. Cette différence biologique responsable de cette distinction justifie tous les abus et même la destruction des animaux au profit exclusif des humains. Au XVII siècle la théorie mécaniciste de la nature des organismes vivants, appliquée par Descartes aux animaux, a corroboré l’héritage moral judéo-chrétien. Cet article présente d’abord la thèse de Descartes sur la quelle la philosophie morale traditionnelle se bâtit; en deuxième place vient la reconstitution des arguments conservateurs directe ou indirectement dérivés de cette tradition. Finalement il montre les risques et les limites de l’adoption de ces arguments en ce qui concerne la morale contemporaine, affectant non seulement les intérêts des animaux mais aussi ceux des sujets humains non paradigmatiques.
78. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
Ricardo Santos O Que é o Monismo Anómalo?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The aim of this paper is to present, in a clear and accessible way, Donald Davidson’s anomalous monism. I stress that what distinguishes Davidson’s monism from other identity theories of the mind is the conjunction of an identity thesis (viz. every mental event is a physical event) with an anti-reductionist argument, according to which there are no strict psychophysical laws.
79. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
Adelino Cardoso Psicologia e Moral em Descartes
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Ce travail vise à poser la continuité entre la psychologie et la morale ainsi qu’à reconnaît re la discontinuité entre celle-ci et la physique dans la pensée cartésienne. En effet, la détermination de la volonté consiste en un processus qui se déploie sur un fond de passivité. Car la liberté recèle des degrés qui vont de l’indétermination pure du libre arbitre jusqu’à l’inclination infaillible vers tel ou tel acte: l’inclination n’affaiblit ni la puissance de la volonté ni la liberté du sujet moral; tout au contraire elle les accroît. Le sage cartésien n’aspire donc pas à annihiler ses passions, il s’attache plutôt à les régler et à les investir afin d’atteindre la perfection, laquelle perfection s’avère indissociable de l’excès. Dépourvu de tout objet déterminé, le désir, pour sa part, constitue le ressort de cette régulation en ce sens qu’il renforce ou atténue chacune des autres passions.
80. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 25
Teresa Antunes “Push Pin” ou Poesia ? O Problema da Distinção Qualitativa dos Valores no Utilitarismo
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The purpose of this paper is to present the classical problem of knowing if utilitarianism can admit a qualitatively distinction of pleasures or interests, introduced by John Stuart Mill, besides the quantitatively distinction supported by Jeremy Bentham. Moreover, it tries to clarify if the quantity theory of values is consistent with utilitarianism and, even so, if its acceptance does not prevent utilitarians from condemning elitism and speciesist prejudice, as many of them actually do. The claim, here, is that utilitarians can probably still hold that condemnation.