Displaying: 81-100 of 418 documents

0.156 sec

81. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Marcus Rossberg Too Good to be “Just True”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Paraconsistent and dialetheist approaches to a theory of truth are faced with a problem: the expressive resources of the logic do not suffice to express that a sentence is just true—i.e., true and not also false—or to express that a sentence is consistent. In his recent book, Spandrels of Truth, Jc Beall proposes a ‘just true’-operator to identify sentences that are true and not also false. Beall suggests seven principles that a ‘just true’-operator must fulfill, and proves that his operator indeed fulfills all of them. He concludes that just true has been expressed in the language. I argue that, while the seven conditions may be necessary for an operator to express just true, they are not jointly sufficient. Specifically, first, I prove that a further plausible desideratum for necessary conditions on ‘just true’ is not fulfilled by Beall’s proposal, namely that ‘just true’ ascriptions should themselves be just true, and not also false (or equivalently, that the ‘just true’-operator iterates). Second, I show that Beall’s operator does not adequately express just true, but that it merely captures an arbitrary proper subset of the just true sentences. Further, there is no prospect of extending the proposal in order to encompass a more reasonable subset of the just true sentences without presupposing that we have antecedent means to characterize the class of just true sentences.
82. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
J. H. Taylor Is the grain of vision finer than the grain of attention? Response to Block
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In many theories in contemporary philosophy of mind, attention is constitutively linked to phenomenal consciousness (e.g. Prinz 2012). Ned Block (2013) has recently argued that ‘identity crowding’ provides an example of subjects consciously seeing something to which they are unable to attend. Here I examine the reasons that Block gives for thinking that this is a case of a consciously perceived item that we are unable to attend to, and I offer a different interpretation.
83. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Bradley Richards Identity-Crowding and Object-Seeing: A Reply to Block
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Contrary to Block’s assertion, ‘‘identity-crowding’’ does not provide an interesting instance of object-seeing without object-attention. The successful judgments and unusual phenomenology of identity-crowding are better explained by unconscious perception and non-perceptual phenomenology associated with cognitive states. In identity-crowding, as in other cases of crowding, subjects see jumbled textures and cannot individuate the items contributing to those textures in the absence of attention. Block presents an attenuated sense in which identity-crowded items are seen, but this is irrelevant to the debate about phenomenal experience of an object in the absence of object-attention. Finally, even unconscious object perception in identity-crowding likely involves an attention-like selective process.
84. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Ned Block Seeing and Windows of Integration
85. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Moti Mizrahi Why Hypothetical Syllogism is Invalid for Indicative Conditionals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article, I present a schema for generating counterexamples to the argument form known as Hypothetical Syllogism (HS) with indicative conditionals. If my schema for generating counterexamples to HS works as I think it does, then HS is invalid for indicative conditionals.
86. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Ben Bronner Assertions Only?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is standardly believed that the only way to justify an assertion in the face of a challenge is by making another assertion. Call this claim ASSERTIONS ONLY. Besides its intrinsic interest, ASSERTIONS ONLY is relevant to deciding between competing views of the norms that govern reasoned discourse. ASSERTIONS ONLY is also a crucial part of the motivation for infinitism and Pyrrhonian skepticism. I suggest that ASSERTIONS ONLY is false: I can justify an assertion by drawing attention to something that clearly makes the assertion true, or likely true.
87. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Kenny Easwaran Why Countable Additivity?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is sometimes alleged that arguments that probability functions should be countably additive show toomuch, and that theymotivate uncountable additivity as well. I show this is false by giving two naturally motivated arguments for countable additivity that do not motivate uncountable additivity.
88. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Wayne A. Davis Meaning, Expression, and Indication: Reply to Buchanan
89. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
A. J. Cotnoir Beyond Atomism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Contemporary metaphysicians have been drawn to a certain attractive picture of the structure of the world. This picture consists in classical mereology, the priority of parts over wholes, and the well-foundedness of metaphysical priority. In this short note, I show that this combination of theses entails superatomism, which is a significant strengthening of mereological atomism. This commitment has been missed in the literature due to certain sorts of models of mereology being overlooked. But the entailment is an important one: we must either accept superatomism or reject one (or other) of the most widespread theses of contemporary metaphysics.
90. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Fabrizio Cariani Epistemic and Deontic Should
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Probabilistic theories of ‘‘should” and ‘‘ought” face a predicament. At first blush, it seems that such theories must provide different lexical entries for the epistemic and the deontic interpretations of these modals. I show that there is a new style of premise semantics that can avoid this consequence in an attractively conservative way.
91. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Stephan Krämer A Simpler Puzzle of Ground
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Metaphysical grounding is standardly taken to be irreflexive: nothing grounds itself. Kit Fine has presented some puzzles that appear to contradict this principle. I construct a particularly simple variant of those puzzles that is independent of several of the assumptions required by Fine, instead employing quantification into sentence position. Various possible responses to Fine’s puzzles thus turn out to apply only in a restricted range of cases.
92. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Endre Begby The Epistemology of Prejudice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to a common view, prejudice always involves some form of epistemic culpability, i.e., a failure to respond to evidence in the appropriate way. I argue that the common view wrongfully assumes that prejudices always involve universal generalizations. After motivating the more plausible thesis that prejudices typically involve a species of generic judgment, I show that standard examples provide no grounds for positing a strong connection between prejudice and epistemic culpability. More generally, the common view fails to recognize the extent to which prejudices are epistemically insidious: once they are internalized as background beliefs, they quite reasonably come to control the assessment and interpretation of new evidence. This property of insidiousness helps explain why prejudices are so recalcitrant to empirical counterevidence and also why they are frequently invisible to introspective reflection.
93. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Justin Snedegar Negative Reason Existentials
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
(Schroeder 2007) presents a puzzle about negative reason existentials—claims like ‘There’s no reason to cry over spilled milk’. Some of these claims are intuitively true, but we also seem to be committed to the existence of the very reasons that are said not to exist. I argue that Schroeder’s own pragmatic solution to this puzzle is unsatisfactory, and propose my own based on a contrastive account of reasons, according to which reasons are fundamentally reasons for one thing rather than another, instead of reasons for things simpliciter, as has been traditionally held.
94. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Lionel Shapiro Validity Curry Strengthened
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Several authors have argued that a version of Curry’s paradox involving validity motivates rejecting the structural rule of contraction. This paper criticizes two recently suggested alternative responses to ‘‘validity Curry.’’ There are three salient stages in a validity Curry derivation. Rejecting contraction blocks the first, while the alternative responses focus on the second and third. I show that a distinguishing feature of validity Curry, as contrasted with more familiar forms of Curry’s paradox, is that paradox arises already at the first stage. Accordingly, blocking the second or third stages won’t suffice for resolving the paradox.
95. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Jean-Rémy Martin, Jérôme Dokic Seeing Absence or Absence of Seeing?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Imagine that in entering a café, you are struck by the absence of Pierre, with whom you have an appointment. Or imagine that you realize that your keys are missing because they are not hanging from the usual ring-holder. What is the nature of these absence experiences? In this article, we discuss a recent view defended by Farennikova (2012) according to which we literally perceive absences of things in much the same way as we perceive present things. We criticize and reject the perceptual interpretation of absence experiences but we also reject the cognitive view which reduces them to beliefs. We propose an intermediary, metacognitive account according to which absence experiences belong to a specific kind of affective experience, involving the feeling of surprise.
96. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Angela Mendelovici Intentionalism about Moods
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to intentionalism, phenomenal properties are identical to, supervenient on, or determined by representational properties. Intentionalism faces a special challenge when it comes to accounting for the phenomenal character of moods. First, it seems that no intentionalist treatment of moods can capture their apparently undirected phenomenology. Second, it seems that even if we can come up with a viable intentionalist account of moods, we would not be able to motivate it in some of the same kinds of ways that intentionalism about other kinds of states can be motivated. In this article, I respond to both challenges: First, I propose a novel intentionalist treatment of moods on which they represent unbound affective properties. Then, I argue that this view is indirectly supported by the same kinds of considerations that directly support intentionalism about other mental states.
97. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Jonathan Payne Abstraction Relations Need Not Be Reflexive
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Neo-Fregeans such as Bob Hale and Crispin Wright seek a foundation of mathematics based on abstraction principles. These are sentences involving a relation called the abstraction relation. It is usually assumed that abstraction relations must be equivalence relations, so reflexive, symmetric and transitive. In this article I argue that abstraction relations need not be reflexive. I furthermore give an application of non-reflexive abstraction relations to restricted abstraction principles.
98. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
B. R. George Knowing-‘wh’, Mention-Some Readings, and Non-Reducibility
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article presents a new criticisms of reductive approaches to knowledge-‘wh’ (i.e., those approaches on which whether one stands in the knowledge-‘wh’ relation to a question is determined by whether one stands in the knowledge-‘that’ relation to some answer(s) to the question). It argues in particular that the truth of a knowledge-‘wh’ attribution like ‘Janna knows where she can buy an Italian newspaper’ depends not only on what Janna knows about the availability of Italian newspapers, but on what she believes about the matter. This dependence of Janna’s knowledge-‘wh’ on her (possibly false) beliefs is incompatible with the reductive approach.
99. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Dan Moller The Epistemology of Popularity and Incentives
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper discusses two epistemic principles that are important to buyers and sellers: the appeal to popularity and the appeal to incentive structures. I point out the various ways these principles are defeasible, and then offer some examples of them at work in the contexts of hiring, politics and the arts. Finally, I consider why these principles are generally neglected, and conclude that our neglect is unwarranted on both epistemic and moral grounds.
100. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Susanna Rinard Against Radical Credal Imprecision
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A number of Bayesians claim that, if one has no evidence relevant to a proposition P, then one’s credence in P should be spread over the interval [0, 1]. Against this, I argue: first, that it is inconsistent with plausible claims about comparative levels of confidence; second, that it precludes inductive learning in certain cases. Two motivations for the view are considered and rejected. A discussion of alternatives leads to the conjecture that there is an in-principle limitation on formal representations of belief: they cannot be both fully accurate and maximally specific.